Advances in Pure Mathematics, 2011, 1, 367-377
doi:10.4236/apm.2011.16066 Published Online November 2011 (http://www.SciRP.org/journal/apm)
Copyright © 2011 SciRes. APM
The Localization of Commutative Bounded BCK-Algebras
Dana Piciu, Dan Dorin Tascau
Faculty of Mathematics and Computer Science, University of Craiova, Craiova, Rom ania
E-mail: danap@central.ucv.ro, dorintascau@yahoo.com
Received August 11, 2011; revised October 20, 2011; accepted October 30, 2011
Abstract
In this paper we develop a theory of localization for bounded commutative BCK-algebras. We try to extend
some results from the case of commutative Hilbert algebras (see [1]) to the case of commutative BCK-alge-
bras.
Keywords: BCK-Algebra, Commutative BCK-Algebra, Algebra of Fractions, Maximal Algebra of
Quotients, -Closed System, Topology, Localization Algebra
1. Introduction
In 1966, Y. Imai and K. Iséki introduced a new notion
called a BCK-algebra (see [2]). This notion is originated
from two different ways. One of the motivations is based
on the set theory (where the set difference operation play
the main role) and another motivation is from classical
and non-classical propositional calculi (see [2]). There
are some systems which contain the only implication
functor among the logical functors. These examples are
the systems of positive implicational calculus, weak
positive implicational calculus by A. Church, and BCI,
BCK-systems by C. A. Meredith (see [3]).
In this paper we develop a theory of localization for
commutative (bounded) BCK-algebras, and then we deal
with generalizations of results which are obtained in the
paper [1] for case of Hilbert algebras. For some informal
explanations of the theory of localization for others
categories of algebras see [4,5].
The paper is organized as follows: in Section 2 we re-
call the basic definitions and put in evidence many rules
of calculus in (commutative) BCK-algebras which we
need in the rest of paper. In Section 3 we introduce the
commutative BCK-algebra of fractions relative to a
-closed system. In Section 4 we develop a theory for
multipliers on a commutative (bounded) BCK-algebra. In
Section 5 we define the notions of BCK-algebras of frac-
tions and maximal BCK-algebra of quotients for a com-
mutative (bounded) BCK-algebra. In the last part of this
section is proved the existence of the maximal BCK-
algebra of quotients (Theorem 29). In Section 6 we de-
velop a theory of localization for commu tative (bounded)
BCK-algebras. So, for commutative (bounded) BCK-
algebra A we define the notion of localization BCK-al-
gebra relative to a topology
F
on A. In Section 7 we
describe the localization BCK-algebra
F
A
in some spe-
cial instances.
2. Preliminaries
In this paper the symbols and are used for logical
implication, respectively logical equivalence.
Definition 1 ([6]) A BCK-algebra is an algebra
,,1A of type (2,0) such that the following axioms
are fulfilled for every ,,
x
yz A:
(a1) ; 1xx
(a2) If 1
x
yy x, then
x
y;
(B)
 
1xyyz xz
;
(C)

x
yzy xz;
(K)
1xyx
.
In [7] it is proved that the system of axioms {a1, a2, B,
C, K} is equivalent with the system {a2, a3, a4, B},
where:
(a3) ; 11x
(a4) 1
x
x.
For examples of BCK-algebras see [6-8]. If A is a
BCK-algebra, then the relation defined by
x
y
iff
is a partial order on A (which will be called
the natura l order on A; with respect to this order 1 is the
largest element of A. A will be called bounded if A has a
smallest element 0; in this case for
1xy
x
A we denote
*0xx
. If

x
yyy xx
for every
,
x
yA
, then A is called commutative (see [5,9,10]).
We have the following rules of calculus in a BCK-al-
gebra A (see [6,7]):
(c1)
x
yx
;
D. PICIU ET AL.
368
(c2)

x
xy


y;
(c3)
x
yy yx

y
;
(c4)
 
x
yzxz  yz xy ;
(c5) If
x
yzAzxz
, then for every ,
and
y
y
zx z.
Proposition 1 ([9], p. 5) If A is a commutative BCK-
algebra, then relative to the natural ordering, A is a join-
semilattice, where for ,
x
yA:
 
x
yxy yyx x  .
Lemma 2 Let A be a commutative BCK-algebra. For
every ,,
x
yz A there exists
x
zyz
 
and
(c6)
 
x
yzx
,
zyz .
Proof. Since
x
yxy by (c5) we deduce that

,
x
yz
,tx zy 
xzyz 
z,
. Let now such that
. Then
tA
x
ytyt z 
z x
, that is,

txy

z
 
x
yzxzy z.
In [9] (Theorem 8) and [8] (Remark 2.1.32) it is
proved the following result:
Theorem 3 If A is a BCK-algebra, then the following
assertions are equivalent:
1) For every ,,
x
yz A,

x
yz xyxz;
2) For every ,
x
yA,

x
xyxy
;
3) For every ,
x
yA,





.
x
yyxxy
xy y
 

x
A BCK-algebra which verify one of the above equiva-
lent conditions is called Hilbert algebra (or positive im-
plicative BCK-algebra).
If A is a bounded BCK-algebra, we have the following
rules of calculus in A (see [6]):
(c7) If
x
y, then **
y
x
**
;
(c8) **** ,
x
xx
**
x;
(c9)

**
** **
,.
x
yyxxy xy
Remark 1 If A is a bounded commutative BCK-alge-
bra, then for every
x
A,
 
**
000 ,
x
xxx x
that is, A is an involutive BCK-algebra (see [6], p. 115
and [9], p. 10).
For 1,,,
n
x
xx A () we will define 1n
 
112
,,; .
nn
xxxxx xx 
For two elements ,
x
yA and a natural number
we denote
1n
,, ,;
n
x
yxx xy where
indicates the number of occurrences of
n
x
. Clearly, if A
is a Hilbert algebra, then n
x
yxy, for every
.
1n
Let A be a BCK-algebra. A deductive system (or i-filter)
of A is a nonempty subset D of A such that 1D
and
for every ,,
x
yA
if ,,
x
xyD then .
y
D
It is
clear that if D is a deductive system,
x
y and ,
x
D
then .
y
D
We denote by the set of all de-
ductive systems of A. For a nonempty subset

Ds A
,
X
A
we denote by

:
X
DDsA XD (
X
is
called the deductive system generated by X). It is known
that
11
:, ,
X
xA ;1,for some ,,
nn
.x xx
AxxX
In particular for a
, we denote by a the deduc-
tive system generated by
a (a is called principal
and
:1x,for some 1ax n
n
Aa ).

Lemma 4 Let A be a bounded BCK-algebra and
,
x
yA
such that there exists
x
y in A. Then there
exists **
x
y
and

*.
**
x
yx
*y
**
,.
Proof. Clearly,

x
yxy Let tA
such
that Then
**
,.txy
*
****
,.
x
yt x
**
tt

**
y

*
.
t txy
 
 
xyt x 
From (c8) we de-
duce that that is,
**
,y
x
yxy
Definition 2 ([7], p. 944) Let A be a bounded BCK-
algebra. An element
x
A
is called boolean if
*1xx  (clearly, *
x
xA).
We denote by
BA the set of all boolean elements
of A; clearly,
BA0,1.
Lemma 5 ([7]) Let A be a BCK-algebra. Then for
every ,
x
yA
, .

11xyx y
Corollary 6 For a bounded BCK-algebra
x
BA
iff
*1.xx
Remark 2 If
x
BA
*
* *
10,
, that is, then
from Lemma 4 we deduce that
*1,xx

**
*
xx xx

****
xx xx
0xx
hence
*
0,
 that is, *
x
is the
complement of
x
in A.
Boolean elements also satisfy several interesting
properties which can be proved using above corollary
and some arithmetical calculus:
Proposition 7 ([7]) Let A be a bounded BCK-algebra.
Then for every
aBA and ,
x
yA we have:
(c10)
;A
*
aB
(c11)
;xaxaa
(c12)
 
;x ay
***
,;aaaa aa 
ax
ya
(c13)
(c14) ** ;aa
(c15)
ax ;aa
(c16)
;xaaax x
(c17)
**
ax aaa 
**
;x
(c18) If
bBA, then

;ba aab b
(c19)
;axx 
*
axax

*
***
.ax ax
(c20)
Corollary 8 ([7]) Let A be a bounded BCK-algebra.
Then
Copyright © 2011 SciRes. APM
D. PICIU ET AL.369
1) If , then

aBA
 
:;aaxAax 
2) For ,

A

,,0,1BA
,ab B

;abBA
3) is a Boolean algebra (where for
, and .

B Aab,ab *
a b

*
*
ab a b 
Corollary 9 Let A be a commutative BCK-algebra.
For every and

aBA,
y
zA
we have:
(c21)

ayz

y
.a az 
Proof. By (c6) we have
 





 
1
ayaza azyaz
yazyazy azz

   
so (c21) is equivalent with (*)

.ayzy az

az

.az
Clearly, and from
So to prove (*) let
such that and
aazy
zyzy
at
za
tA
y
zt. We have the
intention to prove that
 
 
** .
yazty azz
az yzt


t
Indeed, from



 

 
15
1.
B
c
yztazyz
az ttaaza
ta aat ttt
 
 



Proposition 10 Let A be a commutative BCK-algebra.
Then for every and

,abB A
x
A
.b x
we have:
(c22)
 
ax a

bx
Proof. By (c6) we have


 

1
ax bx
abx xbx
abxa xbb

 


  
 .
Also
 









12
.
C
c
abxx abab
axb ab
axbb

 
 
Definition 3 If 12
,
A
A are BCK-algebras, then
12
:
f
AA

is called morphism of BCK-algebras if

,
f
xyfx fy for every 1
,
x
yA
(if
12
,
A
A

f
are bounded BCK-algebras, then we add the con-
dition ).
00
3. Commutative BCK-Algebra of Fractions
Relative to a -Closed System
In this section by A we denote a commutative bounded
BCK-algebra.
Definition 4 A nonempty subset of A will be
called -closed system of A if and
S
S0
x
yS
for every ,.
x
yS
For a -closed system we define the binary
relation
SA
S
on A by
S
,xy
iff there is
s
SBA such that .
s
xs y
Proposition 11 The relation S
is a congruence on
A.
Proof. Clearly S
is an equivalence relation on A. To
prove the compatibility of S
with the operation , let
,,
x
yz A
such that
S
,xy
(hence there is
s
SB A such that
s
xs y). By (c21) we
deduce
 

,
szx szsx
s
zsyszy

 
and similarly,

,
s
xzsyz that is,
S
y,zxz
 and
xzyz,.
S

We denote
S
AS A
; the commutative BCK- al-
gebra
A
S will be called BCK-algebra of fractions of
A relative to S. For
x
A
we denote by
S
x
the
equivalence class of
x
relative to .
S
Clearly, in
A
S, 1 =
,11:xAx
SS
 = {
x
A: there is
s
SBA 1 such that
s
x},
0 =
0:xA ,0x
SS
 = {
x
A: there is
s
SBA such that
s
xs} = {
x
A: there is
s
SBA such that
x
s} and for every ,
x
yA
,
SS
x
yxS
y

 .
Proposition 12
A
S is a bounded commutative BCK-
algebra, when 0 =
S
s
with

s
SBA

.
Proof. Clearly, if ,
s
tSBA, since
ArstSB and
.rtst
 
S
To prove that, for S
rs

s
SBA
,
S
s
= 0, let .
x
A
We have
SS SSSSS
s
xsxxsxx
 

which is true since
s
sx sx 
.
We denote by
:pA AS
S the canonical surjec-
tive morphism of BCK-algebras (defined by
,
S
px xS
for every
x
A).
Remark 3 Since for every
s
SBA

, }
we deduce that
0sss
0.
S
pS BA
Proposition 13 If
x
A
, then
S
x
BAS
iff
there exists
s
SB A
such that So,
if
*1.xxs
,
x
BA then

.
S
x
BAS
Proof. For
x
A
, we have
 

 

*
*
11
SS
S
xBAS xx
xx



 

S
there exists
s
SBA
11.
s
such that
If
*
xx s

,
x
BA since
Copyright © 2011 SciRes. APM
D. PICIU ET AL.
370
*01xx and
0SBA , we deduce that
S
.
x
BA
S
A
S
:
verify the following property of universality:
Theorem 14 For every bounded commutative BCK-
algebra B and every morphism of bounded BCK-alge-
bras
f
A
B such that there
exists a unique morphism of bounded BCK-algebras



0,BAfS
:
f
AS B
such that S
f
pf
.
Proof. Let ,
x
yA such that
.xy
S
S
Then
there is
s
SBA


 
00
sy fsx
fx fs
 such that

 
 
x fsy
fs fy
.
s
f
xf
 
 yfxf
 

y
So,
:
f
AS
B defined for
x
A by
S



f
x
fx
is correct defined. Clearly,
f
is
morphism of bounded BCK-algebras and S
f
pf
.
The unicity of
f
follows from the fact that is
onto.
S
p
Example 1 If A is a bounded commutative BCK-al-
gebra and
0S
S or is such that 0S
and
, then for

\0SBA
 ,
x
yA,

,xy S
00 ,
x
yxy hence
.
A
SA
Example 2 If A is a bounded commutative BCK-al-
gebra and is an -closed system system such that
(for example or ), then for
every
S
1S
,
SA

SBA
x
yA,

,S
xy
(since 11
x
y
and
hence in this case

1SBA,
1AS .
Definition 5
A
S
TA
is called the BCK-algebra of
fractions of A relative to S.
4. Multipliers on a Commutative Bounded
BCK-Algebra
The concept of maximal lattice of quotients for a dis-
tributive lattice was defined by J. Schmid in [11,12]
(taking as a guide-line the construction of complete r ing of
quotients by partial morphisms introduced by G. Findlay
and J. Lambek (see [13], p. 36). The central role in the
construction of the maximal lattice of quotients for a
distributive lattice due to J. Schmidt in [11] and [12] is
played by the concept of multiplier for a distributive lat-
tice defined by W. H. Cornish in [14].
In this section we develop a theory for multipliers on a
commutative bounded BCK-algebra A.
Definition 6 A subset is called -subset of A
if for every and
aA
x
T
we have . axT
We denote by
TA

T A the set of all -subsets of A.
Clearly (and more generally, if denote
by

Ds A
I
A
 
the set of all increasing subsets of A, then
I
ATA
Remark 4 ).
Clearly, if 12
DD

,,TA then
12 .DTA D
Lemma 15 If
,TA then D
1) 1;D
x
D
2) If
x
y
and , then .
y
D
Proof f . (i). I
x
D
, si,nce 1
A
then 11 .
x
D
3) We have .yxy
partial strong multiplier on A we mean Definition 7 By
a map :,
f
DA where

,DTA such that:
(sm1) For every
x
D
a
,A nd
eB

f
e fx; x e
(sm2) For every
x
D
,

x
fx;
(sm3) If
BA,eD then
 
;
f
eBA
(sm4) For every
x
D
and e

,DBA

.
f
e fx xe
By
A
f
we denote the domain of
dom fT; if
do fA
, we called
f
total.
the languag we wil
m
To simplify
ins
ps 0
e,l use strong multiplier
,1
tead partial strong multiplier using total to indicate
that the domain of a certain multiplier is A.
Examples
defined by 0

x
x
:
A
A1) The ma and
respectively 1
1x
, for every
x
A are total strong
multipliers on A.
2) For
aBA and the map

,DTA
:
a
f
D by A defined
a
f
xax, for every
x
D
is a strong multiplier on Aipal).
If
(called princ
,
a
dom fA
we denote a
f
by a
f
.
Re :mark 5 If
f
DA is a strong multiplier on A
(with
DTA), then
1. Indeed, if in (sm1) we
put e1f
1
, we obtain that for every
x
D,
11 11.fx fxf 
For
,DTA we denote
:
M
, :DAf is aAfD
and
strongmultiplieronA
() ,.
ADT
M
AMD A


,
ii
f
MDA
A
12
,DD T, 1,2,i
For and we
de 12
:
fine 21
f
fD DA by 

21 ,
2 1
f
fx fxfxevery for 12
.
x
DD

Lemma 16 1212
,.fMDDA
f
Proof. If 12
x
DD and

eBA, then




 




 
21
2
1 2
121
12 2
1 2
,
,
c
sm
ex fexfex
efxe fxfx
fx
fxfxfx x
fefeBA
 
 


 



 
12
12
12
12
f f
efx
ef
ffx
ffe

 


by Corollary 8 (since
2

12
,
f
efe BA and if
Copyright © 2011 SciRes. APM
D. PICIU ET AL.
Copyright © 2011 SciRes. APM
371














 


21
4
22
12 1 2
12
12
12 12
,
,
c
sm
c
BA
ef fxefx fx
efx efx
xfe xfe
since if ,
x
yA
such that for every exey
,eA ABA B then in particular, for 0e
we
obtain 00.
x
yxy
12
eD D
x
fefexffe

 
 
 
If A is bounded,
DTA and then is
regular. We denote
0D,D
:.RADAD isaregular subsetofA
Lemma 19 If
12
,,DD TARA then
.ARA
12
DDT
Proof. By Remark 4, 12 Let
.ADDT,
x
yA
such that for every
exey
.BA

12 12
,.
f
fMDDA 
llary 17


,,0,1MA
that is,
ounded commu-
at
Coro is a b
tative BCK-algebra.
12
For every
eDD
,BA 1, 2,i
ii
eD since
12
ee D
1 2
D BA  we have

M
A
ma 16
Proof. The fact this a commutative BCK-
algebra follows from Lem. If

,DTA

,
f
MDA and ,
x
D then

101
x
xf
order on
x and sxince the relation of

M
A is given by 12
f
f iff

12
f
xfx
for every

,
12
x
do
that is,
m fdome ded
01,ff

 wuce that
M
A is bou
p
nded.
18 TheLemma ma

:
ABAMA defined vby


12121 2
1222,
eexeeyeex
eey exeyxy


so
12 .DDRA
We denote

:.
r
M
AfMAdomfTAR A 

Aa
a f for every v
aBA is a morphism of
K-algebras.
Proof. If

,abB A and
Corollary 20
r
M
A is a BCK-subalgebra of
M
A.
bounded BC
,
x
A then
Proposition 21

  



r
M
A is a Boolean subalgebra of
M
A.

22
,
a b
c
ab
fxf fx
axbxabx fx
  
so,
ab
f x
Proof. Let :
f
DA be a strong multiplier on A with
RADTA. Then*:
f
DA,
0,
*
f
xfxfxx for
x
D.
 
AAA
vavb vab
and
We have

0
00
A
vf .
finition 8 called regular if for every De is



 
*
ff xfxfxx
f
x xfxfx




DA
,
x
yA such thaey for every

,BA then
t e
x
.eD
x
y
nded BC
ple, a bouFor examK-algebra AThen for
eDBA and
x
D we have
is regular
 

 





















 
21
4
22
c
sm
c
ef fxefxxfxfx
efx exefxefx
xfeexxfexfe
xfe efefexfe



 



 




 




 






 
*
1111.
efe
xfeefexe ex
*


 


Since we deduce that

DRA
 
1
if

21
dom fdom fextends 2
f
1
f
we say that and
2
,
1
f
xfx for all

2;
x
dom f we w21
rite
f
f
if 1
f
extend2
s
f
. A srong mtultiplier
f
is called
maximal if
f
can not to a strictly larger
don.
Lemma 22 1) If

12
,
be extended
mai
f
fMA,
r
f
MA and

*,
f
f hence *
ffx x1, that is,
r
M
A
is a Boolean algebra (by Coro
Remark 6 The axioms sm3, sm4 were necessary
pr
llary 6).
in the
oof of Proposition 21.
Definition 9 Given two strong multipliers 12
,
f
f on A,
D. PICIU ET AL.
372
1
f
f, 2
f
f, then 1
f
and 2
f
coincide on the
 
12
;mfdom f
veg multiplier

r
do
2) Ery stron
f
M
ltiplier. M
A can be ex-
tended to
ea
a maximal stronmre precisely, g uo
ch principal strong multiplier a
f
with
BA and

 
a
domfTAR A can be uniquely extended to
the total strong multiplier
a
a
f
each cipal
extended to a maximal non-
principal one.
Proof. 1) If by contrary, there exists

1
tdomf
and non-prin
strong m can
om
ultiplier
d
be
suc
f
2
h that
 
12
,
f
tft

since
 
mfR A, then there exists do
BA td
omf
such that


12
ft tt
 

ctory, since tt

2) We fira
12
tt f


.domf
tf
ontradi
st pr
t
ove
t f
that
which is c
f
with

aBA can
mu
not be
extended to a non-principal strong ltiplier. Let

 
a
domfTAR, :
a
D A
f
DA
l stro
and suppose
by contrary that there exists

,DTADD

, (
-png multiplier

,
hence

A R
A) andDT
a nonrincipa
f
MDA
which extends a
f
. Since
f
is non-
ts 00
,
principal, there exis
x
Dx D
 such that
00
.

f
xax Since
,DRAthen there exists

tDBA such th
 
0
,axx atx 
t
a
at

x t
is cont
sin
000
ftf
which
radictoryce .
f
f Hence a
f
is
uniquely extended by a
f
.
Now, let

r
f
MA be non-princi and
:
pal
 
,, ,,
f
 
M
DgM DAdom fgDT AD
and

fdom
g
f (clearly, if
,,
f
Dg M then
D A).
Th
T
e s
A R
et
f
M
is ordered by
1122
,,DgDg iff
12
DD and 11
2D.
g
g Let

,:
kkk K be
a
Dg
chain in .
f
M
Th
en 'k
kK
DD
 
.D
So,

TA
and
dom f:
g
DA

 
defined by
k
g
xg
if
xk
x
D is correctly d(sinefined ce if
kt
x
DD with k by 1),

,tK, then
kt
g
x
gx
).
Clearly,
,
g
MDA and

 dom f
g
f
(since if
,

x
dom fD then
x
D
and ts so there exis
kK, suchk
that
x
D, hence
 
k
g
xg
xfx).
n upperfor the family
:
k
gk Kce by Zo
So,

,Dg

is

a bound
D,
k, henrn’s lemma,
f
M
ex
co
h
n-
tains at least one maximal strong multiplier h whic
.f is non-principal and htends
f, h is also non-principal.
On the Boolean algebra

r
extends e
.f Sinc
M
A we consider the re-
A
lation
defined by

12
,ff A
iff and co-
in
1 2
cide on the intersection ofmains.
Lemma 23 A
f f
their do
is a on

r
couencengr
M
A.
Proof. The reflexivity and the symmetry of A
are
im f let
12 23
,,,A
ff ff
. Therefore 12
,ff, and respevely
23
,ff coincide on the intersection of theomain

01 3
cti
ir ds. If by
contrary, there exists
x
dom fm f such that do
10 30
,
f
xfx since
 
2,domfR A there exists
2
tdomfB A such that
 
1 0
x ftxx
0
3
ft
since
10 30
tfx tf
which is contradictory,

.m f
mediately; torove the transitivity o p A
01 2
bility of A
3
f do The txdom fdom compati-
with on
r
M
A is immediately.
For
r
f
MA we denote by
f
the congruence
class of modulo A
and
f A
 .
rA
MA
Rem Proposition 21 weduce that ark 7 Frome d
A
is
a Booleagebra. n al
Lemma 24 The map

:
A
vBAA

defined by

Aa
vaf
injecti of Boolean al
nd
is anve morphism-
gebras a
.BA RA

fact that
A
v
he
Proof. TA
ma 18. ove th
v is a morphism of Boolean al-
gebras folloTws frome injectivity Lemo pr
of A
v let
,abB A ch that su

AA
va vb. Then
 
,
ab Aa
ff fffxfx


 , or every
abb
,
x
A,
x
Axaxb
 for every hence for
0x
we obtain that 00ab .ba To prove
,
A
vBARA
if by contrary tht ere exis
r12
,
f
fMA such that
12
f
f t (that ishere exists
201
x
dom fdomf such that

10 20
f
x
fx)
and

12 12aaaa
ffffffff
 
 



for every

12
,aBA fxaxfxax
 for
every
aBA and every

.
12
x
dom fdomf
For 0a
and 0
x
x
we obtain that
100 20010

20
f
xxx f
contrry.
xfx fx which
to
is
adic

aBA, a
f
Remark 8 Since for every i
n
s the
unique maximal str a
f


ong multiplier o (by Lemma
22) we can identify a
f
with a
f
. Sce o, sinA
v is in-
jective morphism of lean algras, the elemnts of Booebe
BA can be identiwith th elements of the set fied e

:.BA
a
fa
Lemma 25 In of the identifications made above,
if
view
f
A
(with
r
f
MA and
domfTA RA), then
 
D


.DBAaBAf BA
Proof. Let
:
a
f
.aDBA If by contrary,
BA then
a
ff a
f
f is a non-principal strong
men byultiplier. Th22, (2), Lemma a
f
f c
aximal strong multiplier
an be ex-
tended to a non-principal m
Copyright © 2011 SciRes. APM
D. PICIU ET AL.373
:
f
DA with

.DTA Thus, DD and for
every ,
x
D

 
.
a
f fxfxx

x fxaaf 
Since , then

aDBA

fxxfa
 
,fax that is,

4
sm
D
f is principal
which is contradictory with the assum tion thatp
f
is
non-principal.
mmutative BCK-Algebra of
Quotients
Th section is to define (taking as a guide-
ne the case of distributive lattices) the notions of BCK-
5. Maximal Co
e goal of this
li
algebra of fractions and maximal BCK-algebra of quo-
tients for a commutative bounded BCK-algebra. For
some informal explanations of notions of fraction see [13]
and [5].
Definition 10 A bounded commutative BCK-algebra
A
is called BCK-algebra of fractions of A if:
(f1)
BA is a BCK-subalgebra of
A
;
(f2) For every ,, ,abc Aa b

, there exists
suc

h that aa ab

 an
aBA d
.c BA

a
As a notational co nvenience, we write
A
A
to in-
t dicate tha
A
is a Bf fractiCK-algebra oons of
A
. So,
 
A BA (since for

,,abc BA

with abB
,
if consider

,BA then 00aa b0b

 and

A).
Definition
is the tive)
quo
0cc

 B
11
QA maximal (commuta
BCK-algebra of ts of A iftien
A
QA and for
every commutative anbounded BCK-algebra d
A
with
A
A
, there exists a monomorphism-algebras of BCK
:.iAQA
osition 26 Let A be a commutative and bounded
uch t
Prop
BCK-algebra shat
A
A
. Then
A
is a Boolean
algebra.
Proof. If by contrary,
A
6, there exists
i o
Corollary
s not a Bolean algebra,
then by
x
A
such that
*1.x Since x
A
A
, then there exists
eBA,
such that

exBA and

11.e e 
emma 4,
 
ex exe 
*
xx
Then, by L



***
**
**
11
1
11 1,
xex
exeexx
exx exx

 

a contradiction!
Remark 9 If A is a Boolean algebra, then
.BA A
By Proposition 26,
QA is a Boolean alge
ax
bra and the
ioms sm1-sm4 are equivalent with sm1, hence
QA is
in this case just the cal Dedekind-MacNeille com-
pletion of A (see [12], p. 687). In contrast to thral
situation, the Dedekind-MacNeille completion of a Boo-
lean algebra is again distributive and, in fact, is a Boolean
algebra (see [15], p. 239).
Lemma 27 Let
classi
e gene
A
A
; then for every ,,ab A

ab
, and any finite sequence 1n
ists
,,cc

,A
there
ex
aBA sucaa ab

 andh that
iBA for 1, 2,,inac

(n
Proo lemma hol1. So we
2).
for nf. Assumeds true may
bBA such thatfind ba bb

and
i
c BA
 for 1, 2,,1.inb
Since
A
A
, we
find
cBA such that
cb
cba
and b

nBA

ed proper
cc . The

cB the
requirties.
Let
element abA has
.aA

Lemma 28
A
A
and Then



TBA
  :
aa BABAAR
 .
Proof. If
Daa
aBA, then
x
aBA
 and a
x
D
and since
ax aaxa

 B A
it follows
,
a
xDa
 he

.
To provence a

BADT
a
DRA
consider ,
x
yA
such that exey,
for every
.A
a
D
 ntrary,
eB If by co
x
y
, since
A
A
, the
re exists a such that

BA
0
0
aaB
 0a
D
) and 00
,axay
s contradictory
A
(that
.
is,
a
which i
Theorem 29
A
(definection 4)l
(commutative) BCK-algebra o
ed in S is the maxima
f quotients of A.

QA
Proof. The fact that
BA is a BCK-subalgebra
(Boolean subalgebra) of
QA follows fromemma 2 L4
and Remark 8. To prove
,
A
QA let
,,
f
ghQA wit

,r
h ,
f
gh MA such that
g
h (that is, there

exists
0
x
dom gdomh
such that
00
g
x
Put
hx
).

domfTA R
and
D A



[] :.BA fBA
fa
Then
D af


.
f
DBAD
by Lemma 25, If suppose
that for every
,
aa
fgfh
,BA
then
aD
,
aa
fg fh

 
 ev
hence forery
x
domgdom h we have


logou
aa
fgx fhx (anasly than as in the
proof of Lemma 24)

.xagx ahx  axgx axh 
Since
DRA we

g
xhxdeduce that for
every
x
domgdom h so
,
g
h which is
contradce, if ictory. Hen
,
g
h then there exists
,BAaD such that
.
a
But for
this
a
fg hf
A we have

a
ffBA aDB(since
[]
f
DBAD

.
A
QA
of QA
) hence
To aximalityt prove the m, le

A
be a
Copyright © 2011 SciRes. APM
D. PICIU ET AL.
374
bounded commuK-algebrah that
A
A
(t2) If 12
,DDF
, then
Exam 12.DDF
ple 3 If
tative BC suc,
thus
 
;BA BA
Then
A
isdded i
, then the set D emben
QA
by

:iA QA
defined by

,
a
ia f
fo
aA

aa
f D

(see Lemma 28).
Clea
r every
,
where dom
rly,

ar
f
M
obras
of i, let a
A
(by Lemm is a mor-
f BCK-algeemma 18). To prov
injectivity ,,bA

such that
a 28) and i
phism (see Le the
 
ab ab
f
ffxfx
 
  for every .
ab
x
DD

If ,ab

by Lemmce a 27 (sin
A
A
)

b BA
a
a b
 which is contradictoe

b BA
iab
).
1. If A is a BCK-algebra with
nd
, th
nd
ry (sinc
aDD

ere exists

A such that
a a
,a

Remark 10
 
2
0,1 L a
aB
aa
BA
,aa
mplies
a
A
A

0,1 , then A hence
TA
D:
F
D DTAD
 
recall tha
is a topological system on A.
denote the set
of all regular subsets of
Example 4 Wet by

RA we
A (see Definition 8). Then
F
TA RA is a topologystem on A (see
Lemma 19). SA a -closed subset of A (see
Definition 4). I
ical s
Example 5 Let
f we denote by

:,
SDTADBAFS
  then S
F
is a
topological system on A.
is a topological system on A, l
F
If et us consider the
relation
F
of A defined by: there exists

,F
xy

DF
such that txty for any
.tDBA
As in the case of S
(see Prop deduce that osition 11), we
F
is a congruence
We shall denoty
on A.
be

2.A L Indeed, if ,,abc A
Q
, with a

A sat e(hence

.ecBA 0,e he

,cBA th

.
b, then
b,
nce
there exists eB
) and
at is
uch th
Clearly,
ae
1e
A
F
x
the congruence class of an
ment
BA Asof BCK-
ras wiy we have BCK-alg
hains.
2. More general, if A is a BCK-algebra such that
opert
examples
local
algeb
and
th this pr
BCK-c
ebras
ele
x
A
and by :
F
F
pA A
the canonical
mras.
1 C
orphism of BCK-algeb
Remark 1learly, if

.
FF
BA

Definition 13 A
aBAa
F
-multip
BA
is finite, if
A
A
lier on A is a mapping
then

,
A
BA hence
der
d
consi
 
A BA
Indeed, A
an.aA
Q

BA
BA be-
ing finite, there exists a smallest element
eBA
, then there
ae
a
a
such a
e Suppose a
e
would exists

eBA such that
a
ee
and ut ea ,
a
ee

.aBA

.eaBA B
aa

BA implies
and thus we ob

a
eae
a conce
,a that is

.
tain
tradiction. Hen
,ae
,
ea e
aBAa
a
e
A
BA
Then

,
A
BA
hence

.BA
ded
QA
Boun
e localization lattice
ation otative6. Localizf
BCK-ALgebras
Com
it
mu
ed th
[4], G. Georgescu exhibIn
F
L
of a distributive lattice L with respect to a topology
F
on
see
L in a similar way as for rings (see [16]) or monoids (
[17]). The aim of this section is to define the notion of
localization BCK-algebra
F
A
of a commutative bound-
ed BCK-algebra A with respect to a topology
F
on A. In
the last part of this section proved that the maximal
commutative BCK-algebra of quotients (defid in Sec-
tion 5) and the commutative BCK-algebra of fractions
relative to a -closed system (defined in Section 3) are
BCK-algebras of localization.
In this section A will be a bounded commutative
BCK-algebra and
is
ne
F
a topological system on A.
Definition 12 A non-empty family
F
of elements on

TA will be called a topological system on A if the
following properties hold:
If

12
,DFDTA and 12
,DD then
2
DF (hence
(t1)
A
F);
:
F
fD A
where DF
such that for every
BA and ,a
x
D
(m1)

;
F
f
a
(m)
x ax
f
.
x
2Ffx
, then a
F
F
A-multiplier is a function
ich ve only the conditions sm1 and sm2
If
:Arifyf
fro
A wh
Definitiom n 7. Theaps 0,1:
m
F
AA
, defined by
0
F
xx
and 1
1
F
x
for every
x
A
are
F-multipliers. Also, for

aBA, :
aF
fD A
de-
fined by
aF
x aF
xf
 for every ,
x
D
is a
F-multiplier (where DF
).
For DF
, we shall denote by

,
F
MDA
t
s havithe domain . If
he set
of all the F-multiplierng D
12
,,DD F
12
DD we have aapping canol mnica
12
,21
:, ,
D
DF F
MDA MDA

defd by ine
12 1
,DD
D
ff
for

2,.
F
MDA
Let us consider f
the directed system of sets


,,MDAF
D
F
F
A
12 121 2
,,,
DD DDFD D
and denote by the inctive
limit (in the category
du
of sets):
li ,
DF
m
F
F
AMDA

.
For any F-multiplier :
F
fD A
y

we shall denote b
,Df the equivalence class of in f
F
A
.
Remark 12 We recall that if :
i
fi F
D A
, 1,2i
multipliers, then

F-are 112 2
f(in,,DfD
F
A
) iff
ere exists ,DFD DD
th 12
 such that 12
.
D
D
ff
Let :F
fD A
ii
, (2), Fulti- with ,1,DFi
ppin
i
pliers. Let usg
-m
consider the ma
1212
:
F
ffDDA
, defined by

12 1 2
,
f
fx fxfx for any 12
,
x
DD
and let
Copyright © 2011 SciRes. APM
D. PICIU ET AL.375

11221212
,, ,DfDfD Dff .
This definition is correct. Indeed, let :
ii F
fD A

,
with ,1,2
i
DFi

such that

,
ii
Df,
ii
Df

,
Then there such that
1, 2iexist 12
,DD
 
.
1
D

F
2
D
and
112 2
,DDD
 
 
D11
,
DD
 
11
ff
2
222
DD
 
12 12
DDD DD
 

.ff
If we set
12
DD
 , then DF

and
clearly

12 12
,
DD
ff ff
 


hence

121 2121
,,DDff DDff2.
 

ma 30Lem

12 12
,.
F
ffMDDA
 
Proof. If 12
x
DD
and n

aBA, the

 





21
1
()
12
/
FF
c
F
2
12
12
f
fax xax f
afxa
affx




and
 

fa
fx
2
12122.
m
F
ffxfxfxfxx

rollary 31Co

,,0,1
F
A is a bounded commutative
Bre CK-algebra (whe

0,A0 and

1,1
A
) (see Co-
rollary 17).
Definition 14
F
A
will be called the localization BCK-
algebra of A with respect to the topology
F
.
Lemma 32 The mapping

:
F
F
vBA deAfined by


,
F
a
a Af for every orphism of
v is a m
BCK-algebras a
is a re

aBA
nd

F
vBAgular subset of
F
A
.
Proof. If
,ab B A then
 



,
,, .
b
ab abF
v bAf,
FFa
v aAf
A
ff Afvab
 
 
To prove that is a regular subset of

F
vA
F
A
, let

,,
ii F
Df A,1,2i, such that
i
DF




11
,,,
aa22
,
A
fDfAf every
Then
Df
for

aBA.

112 2
,,
aa
Df fDff there exists
such that
12
DFDD,D

  
12
12
,
aa
DD
FF
ff
axfx axfx


 
for every
ff
x
D
oose
and If in this last equiva-

aBA.

BA
lence we ch0,athen we obtain that

 
12FF
xf fx
12 1122
,,,
xx
f
xfxDfDf

 
hence

F
vBA is a regular subset of
F
A
.
7. Applications
that follows we describe the localization BCK-algebra
In
F
A
in some special in
1) If
stances.
DTA and
F
is the topological system
:
D
F
DTADD
  (see Example 3), then
,
F
AF
MDA
and

:
F
F
A AvB is defined by

,
FaD
v
,
x
yBA
aor any

aBA. For
Df f
we have
,F
xy
for every

,x
Dx 
njective m of BC
FF
yD
tDtf v 
there exists an iorphism K-algebras
xty f vy then
:,
F

FFF
A
A
x
vx
such that
.
F
F
vp
2) To obtain the maximal BCK-algebra of quotients
QA as a locization relative tol system al a topologica
F
we will develop another theory of F-multipliers
(mDef
str
eaning we add new axioms for F-multipliers).
inition 15 Let F be a topological system on A. A
ong-F-multiplier is a mapping :
F
fD A
(where
DF
) which verifies the axioms m1 and m2 and
(m3) If
,eDBA then
 
F
fe BA
;
(m4)
FF

,
x
fa a

 ry fx for eve
BA and .
x
D
aD
If
, then
F
A
F
is the identity congruence of A
so ulti is a strong tot(in
sense of Defini.
mark 13
a str al multiplier
tion 7)
ong F-m plier
Re If A is a BCK-algebra, the maps 0,1:
F
AA
defined by 0
F
xx
and 1
1
F
x
for every
x
A
are strong F-multipliers. If
:
ii F
D Af
, (with ,1,2
i
DFi
) are strong F-mul-
mapping tipliers, the 1 221
:
F
f AfDD

by
defined

12 1 2
,
f
f
12
x fxfx for any
x
DD
is also a stier.
Remark 14 Analog tipliers if
we we obtain
of
rong-F-multipl
ous as in the case of F-mul
work with strong-F-multipliers a BCK-
subalgebra
F
A
denoted by
F
s
A which will be
called the strong localization BCK-algebra of A with
respect to the topological system F.
If
,
F
TA A then R is th
F
e identity con-
gruence of A and we obtain the definition for strong
multipliers on A, so

lim
F
A
M,DA
DF

tion it is easy to see that
. In this situa-
F
v is injective, so we have:
Proposition 33 In t

,
he case

F
IARA
F
s
A
is exactly theve BCK-alge- maximal commutati
bra of quotients
QA o (see Section 5, Theorem 2f A9).
call (see
Propos
3. Let S be a -closed sy
ition 11) that on A we have the congruence S
stem of A. We re
defined by:
iff there is
s
SBA such
y,S
x
that
s
xsy and
S
AS A
is called the
Copyright © 2011 SciRes. APM
D. PICIU ET AL.
376
system S ( from Section
ase we have the topological system
(commutative) BCK-algebra of fractions of A relative to
the -closed see Remark 5 3). In
this c S
F
associated
with ,S


:.
S
FDTADSBA 
Lemma 34 .
S
F
S
Proof. For ,,
x
yA if

,S
F
xy
then there exists
DFS such that
s
xsy for every
s
SBA.
ts


DSBA , so this

Si
0
nce S
DF, ere ex
s
DSB partitain
00
,
A; in cular we ob
s
xs y hence ,
S

,xy
that is, S.
F
S
If

S
,xy
, then 00
,
s
xs 

y for some
0
s
SBA. If :A
pal e system gy

rinci
consider

0
Ds a
deductivenerated
0
sa
0,
(the pb
s
see
Corollary then S
DF

0
8, 1)), (since
s
DSB

A ). If
s
S
00
BA then
s
ssss hence
 

00
,.
S

00
SS
F
SFF S
ss xsx
ssy ys
xy
sx s
ssy
 
 
 

tion 35 If S
 
 
Proposi
F
is the topological
a -closed subset S of n
sy
A, the
stem on A
associated with S
F
s
A
is isomorphic with

.BAS
Proof. Following Lemma 34, ,
S
F
S
therefore a
S
F
-multiplier can be considered inis case as a mg thappin
:
f
DAS (DS
F) having for
x
D and


DBA the properties
a
 
S



,,
.
S
S
fa xafx
x
fa
 x
fa BAS

If
fx



112 2
,, ,lim,
SDF
S
F
DfDfs A,AS

 
and
MD

112 2
,,Df Df then there exists such
th and
S
DF
at 12
DDD 12
.
D
D
f
f
Since
n
12
,,DS
F, the

DD

12
,SBA DA 
are nonem, hence th
,SBA DBD S
ptyere exist
,
s
D

SBA
11
s
DSBA and

22
s
DS

BA.

.
We shall prove that 112 2
f
sfsed, if con- Inde
sider

12 ,tsss DSBA  then

1
 
12111SS
f
tss

 fs fs (since
2SS
ss
0) and an

alogously
 
22112
.
2 2
f
tn a simifsfs fs
 
112 2
Ilar way we
can show that
f
tft for a
,.ttSB
ny
with tese consid-
mapping

A In accordance
12
erations we can define the
Dh
:l
im,
SDF
S
F
s
AM BA
 DAS
 S
by putting

,,Dff s
where

.
s
DSBA It is easy
is a mebras. We
shall prove that
orphism of BC
is injective and surjectiv
the injectivity of
e. To prove

112 2
,, , let
S
F
DfDfs A such
that




112 2
,,.DfDf

Then for any
,
to prove that
K-alg
11
s
DSB

A22
s
DSBA we have
112 2
.
f
sfs For two fixed elements 12
,
s
s with
,
ii
s
DSBA 1,2i
, we consider the element
2

.
12 1
s
ss A We have DD SB

0
12111111S
f
s sfs
 fs fs and

222222
0,
f
2 1S
s s
 henfsfs fs ce
12
.
f
sfs Now t le
ss
12 12
:.DsDD
s
DsD
Sin

 ce
s
s
D
we deduce that .
s
D If aA and
s
s
D
then

.
ss
s
sa s asDD
 
SA Sinc
.
e
s
sS
s
DDDF
  If
s
s
D
, then


11
11
0
S
ss sfsfss
1
s
fsfs fs
 

 
and analogously,


22 12
112 2
12 ,,
ss
DD
fs fsfs fs
,
f
fDfDf


 
that is,
is injective. To prove the surjectivity of
, let
SAS
withaB aA
.
ent
s
S
For fixed elem one we consider
,
:.DsxAsx  Clearly .
S
DF We define
:
a
f
DAS by putting
 
,
aS
fx ax
 for
every .
x
D
Ca
f
ilearly, s a strong S
F
-multiplier
en (clearly (m3) is verified si

,eDBA thnce if

.
SSSa
f
eae a
e
  From BAS


,,
a
Dfa
SS
aS S
sas as
fs a
asa
 

that is,
is surjective, hence bijective.
8. References
Pi of Commu-
e (Unbounded) Hilbert thematical
2, No. 3, 2010, pp. 285-300.
. Iséki, “On Axiom Systems of Proposi-
[1] D. ciu and C. Busneag, “The Localization
tativAlgebras,” Ma
Reports, Vol. 1
] Y. Imai and K[2
tional Calculi XIV,” Proceedings of the Japan Academy,
Vol. 42, No. 1, 1966, pp. 19-22.
doi:10.3792/pja/1195522169
[3] A. N. Prior, “Formal logic, 2nd Ed,” Oxford, 1962.
[4] G. Georgescu, “F-Multipliers and the Localization of
Distributive Lattices,” Algebra Un
2-3, 1985, pp. 181-197.
iversalis, Vol. 21, No.
.1007/BF01188055doi:10
ra of
ems in
[5] S. Rudeanu, “Localizations and Fractions in Algeb
Logic,” Journal of Multi-Valued Logic & Soft Computing,
Vol. 16, No. 3-5, 2010, pp. 465-467.
[6] R. Cignoli and A. Torens, “Glivenko Like Theor
Copyright © 2011 SciRes. APM
D. PICIU ET AL.
Copyright © 2011 SciRes. APM
377
Natural Expansions of BCK-Logic,” Mathematical Logic
Quarterly, Vol. 50, No. 2, 2004, pp. 111-125.
doi:10.1002/malq.200310082
[7] J. Gispert and A. Torrens, “Boolean Representation of
Bounded BCK-Algebras,” Soft Computing, Vol. 12, No.
10, 2008, pp. 941-954. doi:10.1007/s00500-007-0261-0
[8] A. Iorgulescu, “Algebras of Logic as BCK-Algebras,”
,
. J. R. Salas, “Negation and BCK-
ASE, Bucharest, 2008.
[9] K. Iséki and S. Tanaka, “An Introduction to the Theory of
BCK-Algebras,” Mathematica Japonica, Vol. 23, No. 1
1978, pp. 1-25.
[10] F. M. G. Olmedo and A
Algebras,” Mathematical Logic Quarterly, Vol. 49, No. 4,
2003, pp. 336-346. doi:10.1002/malq.200310035
[11] J. Schmid, “Multipliers on Distributive Lattices
ocietatis János Bolyai,
1966.
o. 2, 1974, pp.
and
Rings of Quotients,” Houston Journal of Mathematics,
Vol. 6, No. 3, 1980, pp. 401-425.
[12] J. Schmid, “Distributive Lattices and Rings of Quo-
tients,” Colloquia Mathematica S
Vol. 33, Szeged, Hungary, 1980.
[13] J. Lambek, “Lectures on Rings and Modules,” Blaisdell
Publishing Company, New York,
[14] H. Cornish, “The Multiplier Extension of a Distributive
Lattice,” Journal of Algebra, Vol. 32, N
339-355. doi:10.1016/0021-8693(74)90143-4
[15] R. Balbes and Ph. Dwinger, “Distributive Lattices,” Uni-
versity of Missouri Press, Columbia, 1974.
[16] N. Popescu, “Abelian Categories with Applications to
Rings and Modules,” Academic Press, New York, 1973.
.
[17] B. Strenström, “Platnes and Localization over Monoids,”
Mathematische Nachrichten, Vol. 48, No. 1-6, 1971, pp
315-334. doi:10.1002/mana.19710480124