Journal of Quantum Informatio n Science, 2011, 1, 35-42
doi:10.4236/jqis.2011.12005 Published Online September 2011 (http://www.SciRP.org/journal/jqis)
Copyright © 2011 SciRes. JQIS
A New Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics
Shiro Ishikawa
Department of Mat hematics, Faculty of Science an d Te ch n ol ogy, Keio University, Hiyoshi, Yokohama, Japan
E-mail: ishikawa@math.keio.ac.jp
Received July 17, 2011; revised August 1, 2011; accepted August 15, 2011
Abstract
The Copenhagen interpretation is the most authorized interpretation of quantum mechanics, but there are a
number of ideas that are associated with the Copenhagen interpretation. It is certain that this fact is not nec-
essarily desirable. Thus, we propose a new interpretation of measurement theory, which is the linguistic as-
pect (or, the mathematical generalization) of quantum mechanics. Although this interpretation is superficially
similar to a part of so-called Copenhagen interpretation, we show that it has a merit to be applicable to both
quantum and classical systems. For example, we say that Bell’s inequality is broken even in classical sys-
tems.
Keywords: the Copenhagen Interpretation, Quantum and Classical Measurement Theory, the Law of Large
Numbers, Maximum Likelihood Estimation, Kolmogorov Extension Theorem, Wavefunction
Collapse, Bell’s Inequality
1. Introduction
It is well known (cf. [1]) that quantum mechanics is for-
mulated in an operator algebra (i.e., an operator
algebra composed of all bounded linear operators on a
Hilbert space H with the norm

BH

=
BH
F=1
sup uH
H
F
u) as follows:






physics
probabilistic interpretationkinetic equation
quantum mechanics
quantum measurementcausality
A

Also, the Copenhagen interpretation due to N. Bohr (et
al.) is characterized as the guide to the usage of quantum
mechanics (A). Although quantum mechanics (A) with
the Copenhagen interpretation is generally accepted as
one of the most trustworthy theories in science, it should
be noted that there is no definitive statement of the Co-
penhagen interpretation, that is, there are a number of
ideas that are associated with the Copenhagen interpreta-
tion. We do not think that this fact is desirable.
Measurement theory (mentioned in Section 2 later or
refs. [2-6]) is, by an analogy of the (A), constructed as
the mathematical theory formulated in a certain C*-alge-
bra A (i.e., a norm closed subalgebra in , cf. [7])
as follows:

BH


language
measurement theoryB


Rule 1 in Section 2Rule 2 in Section 2
measurementcausality
Note that this theory (B) is not physics but a kind of
language based on the mechanical world view since it is
a mathematical generalization of quantum mechanics
(A).
When
=c
BH
, the C*-algebra composed of all
compact operators on a Hilbert space H, the (B) is called
quantum measurement theory (or, quantum system the-
ory), which can be regarded as the linguistic aspect of
quantum mechanics. Also, when is commutative (that
is, when is characterized by , the C*-algebra
composed of all continuous complex-valued functions
vanishing at infinity on a locally compact Hausdorff
space

0
C
(cf. [7])), the (B) is called classical measure-
ment theory. Thus, we have the following classification:




0
when
when
measurement theory
quantum measurement theory
=classical measurement theory
c
BH
C
C

That is, this theory covers several conventional system
theories (i.e., statistics, dynamical system theory, quan-
tum system theory).
The purpose of this paper is to propose an interpreta-
tion of measurement theory (B). Since the (C) says that
this interpretation should be common in classical and
36 S. ISHIKAWA
quantum measurement theories, it is also regarded as a
new interpretation of quantum mechanics.
2. Measurement Theory
Now we shall explain the measurement theory (B). Let
be a -algebra, and let be the dual
Banach space of . That is,


BH*
C

is a continu-
ous linear functional on , and the norm
is
defined by

()
sup {suchthat=BH
FF F
F
1. Define the mixed state such that
=1
and
And define the mixed state space such that

0 for allthat0.FF F
such

m
S

is a mixed state.
m

S
2
 (1)
A mixed state ) is called a pure state if
it satisfies that

m
S
1
=1
 

for some 12
,

and 0<
m
S
<1
implies 1
==
2
 
. Put

is a pure state.
pm


SS
(2)
which is called a state space. It is well known (cf. [7])
that

*
()=
pc
BH uuS (i.e., the Dirac notation)
=1
H
u, and


*
000
pC
S is a point
measure at , where
0

 
0
0dff
 

. The latter implies that
0
fC
*
0
pCS
can be also identified with such as


*
00
0
pC

S
*
.
Here, assume that the -algebra
C

BH has
the identity
I
. This assumption is not unnatural, since,
if , it suffices to reconstruct the above such
that it includes
I 

I
. According to the noted idea (cf.
[8]) in quantum mechanics, an observable
O:= X, ,
F
in is defined as follows:
1) [Field]
X
is a set,

P
X, the power set of
X
is a field of
X
, that is, “12
,1 2
 ”,
”.
\X 
2) [Finite additivity]
F
is a mapping from to
satisfying: a): for every
, is a non-
negative element in such that

F
0

F
I , b):
and

=0F

=
F
XI
, where 0 and I is the 0-ele-
ment and the identity in respectively. c): for any
finite decomposition

of
12
,,,,,
n
  
N
, it holds that
..,,(= 1,ieF n 

=ij
=1
2,3,,),= ,
N
nn
N 


N
n
FF
n
ij
=1
n

.
Remark 1 [Countable additivity] The assumption of
the countable additivity (i.e.,


=1
lim N
Nn
n
F

 
F
in the sense of weak-topology ) may be rather half-fin-
ished. If the countable additivity is required, it is, by the
reason mentioned in Remark 3 and 6 later, recommended
to start from the -algebra
*
W such that 
BH as discussed in Appendix later (cf. [5]). However,
our interest in this paper is not mathematics but the in-
terpretation of measurement theory. Thus, all arguments
will be discussed under the above finite additivity (i.e., 1)
and 2)).
With any system S, a -algebra
*
C

BH can
be associated in which the measurement theory (B) of
that system can be formulated. A state of the system S is
represented by an element and an ob-
servable is represented by an observable

p
S
=, ,O:
X
F
in . Also, the measurement of the observable for O
the system S with the state
is denoted by

MO,S

(or more precisely,
MO:=(,,),
X
FS

). An ob-
server can obtain a measured value
x
X by the
measurement

MO,S
The Rule 1 presented below is a kind of mathematical
generalization of Born’s probabilistic interpretation of
quantum mechanics (A). And thus, it is a statement
without reality.
.
Rule 1 [Measurement] The probability that a meas-
ured value
x
X obtained by the measurement

0
MO:=(,,),XFS
belongs to a set
 is
given by
0F
.
Remark 2 Again note that Rule 1 is a statement with-
out reality (i.e., a kind of incantation or spell). Thus, it is
unnecessary (or precisely speaking, impossible) to an-
swer the question: “What is measurement (or, system,
state, observable, probability, etc.)?” However, surpris-
ingly, as seen in [2-6] or Section 4 later, man’s linguistic
competence enables us to use Rule 1. This is essential to
our approach to the interpretation of quantum mechanics.
Next, we explain Rule 2 in (B). Let
11
BH
and
22
BH
1,2 :
be -algebras. A continuous lin-
ear operator
*
C
2 1

2
is called a Markov opera-
tor, if it satisfies that 1): for any non-
negative element

1,2 20F
F
in , ii): 1,2 21
2

=
I
I, where
k
I
is the identity in
1,2.,=k
k
Here note that, for any
observable
22
O:=, ,
X
F in 2 the ,

1,2 2
,,
X
F
1,2 2
O.
is an observable in , which is denoted by
1
Also, the dual operator clearly satisfies
that
** *
1,2 12
:
*
1, 2

**
12
mm
SS.
Let
,T
be a tree, i.e., a partial ordered finite set
such that 1
t3
t
and 2
tt
3
implies or
1
tt221
tt
.
Assume that there exists an element , called the
root of T, such that () holds. Put
0
tT
tT
0
tt
2
tt
22
12
=,Ttt 1
T
.
C
opyright © 2011 SciRes. JQIS
37
S. ISHIKAWA
Definition 1 [Markov relation] The family
12
,:
tt
is called a Markov relation (due to
21
12 2
(, )
tt
tt T

the Heisenberg picture), if it satisfies the following con-
ditions 1) and 2).
1) With each , a -algebra is associated.
tT

,tt
*
C
2
Tt
2) For every 12 , a Markov operator
1
t
is defined. And it satisfies that
holds for any , .

12
,tt
12
,:
tt
12 23
,,tt tt

2
t

=tt
13
,
The family of dual operators

2
23
,ttT
 
1212 12
** *
,2
(, )
:mm
tttt tt T
SS
is called a Markov relation (due to the Schrödinger pic-
ture). However, it is not formally used in measurement
theory.
Now Rule 2 in the measurement theory (B) is pre-
sented as follows:
Rule 2 [Causality] The causality is represented by a
Markov relation .


1221 12
,2
,
:
tttt ttT

Remark 3 If an infinite tree T is required, we must start
from a -algebra
*
W (cf. Appendix later). However,
in this paper, we, for simplicity, assume the finiteness of
. Also, by the same reason mentioned in Remark 2, the
question: “What is causality?” is nonsense. What we can
do in measurement theory is only to trust in man’s lin-
guistic competence.
T
3. An Interpretation of Measurement
Theory
The measurement theory (B) asserts “Describe any ordi-
nary phenomenon according to Rules 1 and 2”. Still,
most readers may be perplexed how to use Rules 1 and 2
since there are various usages. Thus, the following prob-
lem is significant.
(D) How should Rules 1 and 2 be used?
Note that reality is not reliable since Rules 1 and 2 are
statements without reality. Thus, we want to define the
new interpretation such that
(E) the new interpretation is a guide to the most useful
(or, powerful, “Occam’s razor”-like) usage of
Rules 1 and 2.
Now we can present our main assertion in this paper
as follows:
(F) The new interpretation defined in the (E) is charac-
terized as the following (F1) – (F3).
Here,
(F1) Consider the dualism composed of “observer” and
“system (= measuring object)”.
(F2) Only one measurement is permitted. And thus, the
state after a measurement is meaningless since it
can not be measured any longer.
(F3) The causality should be assumed only in the side
of system, however, a state never moves. Thus, the
Heisenberg picture should be adopted. Also, the
observer does not have the space-time. Thus, the
question: “When and where is a measured value
obtained?” is meaningless,
and so on.
The above may be rather similar to a certain part of so
called Copenhagen interpretation. However, note that we
do not assume “the state after a measurement (= wave-
function collapse)” and “the Schrödinger picture”, which
are often investigated in so-called Copenhagen interpre-
tation.
Also, some may consider that the above proposal (F)
is too optimistic, since the following question is not yet
answered:
(G) Does the most useful usage of Rules 1 and 2 exist?
Or, is it determined uniquely?
However, we may be allowed to be optimistic until
another most useful usage (or, a powerful rival candidate)
will be discovered. In other words, we expect the readers
to read the overwhelming predominance of the (F) in the
following section or refs. [2-6].
4. Examples and Remarks
What we want to assert in this paper is only the (F). Thus,
it is desirable that the each one reader verifies the supe-
riority of the (F) in our papers [2-6]. However, in this
section we take up some simple examples, which pro-
mote the readers’ understanding of the (F). Note, for
completeness, that all examples are consequences of
measurement theory with the interpretation (F).
Example 1 [Parallel measurement, the law of large
numbers] For each , consider a measure-
ment
=1,2, ,k

K
MO:= []
,,,XFS
.
k
kkkk
k
However, the in-
terpretation (F2) says that only one measurement is per-
mitted. Thus, we consider the spatial tensor -algebra
*
C
=1=1 ,
kk kk
BH
K
KK
and consider the product space
=1kk
X
and the product field =1 k
, which is defined
by the smallest field that contains a family
K
k

=1 ,=1,2, ,
K
kkkk
kK
.
Define the parallel observable
=1=1 =1
O,
KKK
kk kkkk
,
X
F
*K
in the tensor -algebra such that
C=1k
k
 
=1 =1
=,=
kk kkkk k
KK 1,2,,.
F
FkK
Then, the above

=1
MO,
kk
K
kk
S
is represented
Copyright © 2011 SciRes. JQIS
38 S. ISHIKAWA
by the parallel measurement
=1 =1
=1
MO
KK
kk kk
K
kk
S




=1 MO,
kk
K
kk
S
=k


O= ,, =XF
,
which is also denoted by . Consider
a particular case such that, ,

,, ,
kkk
X
F Let

1,2,,.kK

12
,, ,= =
k

K
x
xx

K
X
=1
K
k
be a measured value by the parallel measure-
ment . Then, using Rule 1, we see the
law of large numbers, that is, for sufficiently large K,

MO,S




#1,2,,
k
kKx
F
K


#[ ]

holds (cf. [2,4]), where
A
is the the number of ele-
ments of the set A. This is, of course, most fundamental
in science. Also, this is the reason that the term “prob-
ability” is used in Rule 1.
Notation 1 It is natural to consider
that a measurement is usually





MO:=,, ,XFS
MO,S
taken in order to know the state
. Thus, when we want
to emphasize that we do not know the state ,
the me-
asurement MO is often denoted by


,S
MO, .S


Remark 4 [Maximum likelihood estimation in classical
measurements] Consider the classical cases in (C). It
may be usual to consider that Rule 1 leads the following
statement (cf. [3,4]), i.e., maximum likelihood estimation
in classical measurements:
(H) When we know that a measured value obtained by
a measurement
1
,
0111
:=,,
C
MO
X
FS
1

*
00
*pC
 S
be-
longs to , there is a reason to infer that
the unknown state

where
1


*
0
pC
0
S is defined by

011=F


11
F
0
if it exists.


0*
pC
S
max
Although this (H) is surely handy, note that the (F2)
says that it is illegal to regard the
as the state after
the measurement . Thus, strictly speak-

0
C


1
MO,S
ing, the (H) is informal. And thus, it should be reconsid-
ered in Example 2 below.
Example 2 [Maximum likelihood estimation in meas-
urements] By a similar method as the lead of the (H), we
can easily see the following statement (I), which should
be regarded as the measurement theoretical form of ma-
ximum likelihood estimation (cf. Corollary 5.5 in [4]).
(I) When we know that a measured value obtained by a
measurement

, ,
1212 []
MO:= ,
X
XF
S
2
1
belongs to
X
, there is a reason to infer that
the probability that the measured value belongs to
12
22
 is given by the following con-
ditional probability:


01
01
F
2
2
FX

(3)
where
p
S
0
is defined by

012
FX

12
FX
ma xp
S if it exists. Here, note that the
0
is not the state after the measurement

MO, .S
This (I), which also includes quantum cases, is most
fundamental in statistics, and thus, we believe (cf. [2-6])
that statistics is one of aspects of measurement theory.
For the relation between the informal (H) and the formal
(I), see Remark 5 later.
Example 3 [Simultaneous measurement] For each
, consider a measurement
=1,2, ,kK


,, ,
kkkk
XFS
MO:=
.
However, since the (F2) says that only one measurement
is permitted, the

=1
,MO
K
kk
S
should be recon-
sidered in what follows. Under the commutativity condi-
tion such that


,,
=,
jjii
j
F F
ij
=
ijj
ii j
FF
FF
i

  (4)
we can define the simultaneous observable
=1 =1
,
KK
kkk
=
O=
KK
kk 1 =1
,
kkk
X
F
 in such that
=1 =
,=
KK
k k
kk
 

11 22
1,,.
K K
FFFF
kK
=1kk
 
 

(5)
Then, the above


=1
MO,
K
kk
S
is, under the
commutativity condition (4), represented by the simulta-
neous measurement

=1
MO,
K
kk
S
.
Remark 5 [The relation between (H) and (I)] Consider
the (I) in the classical cases, i.e., . And as-
sume the simultaneous observable 12

0
=C
=
F
FF in (3).
Then, putting 00
=
(i.e., the point measure at 0
),
we see that


 

11 2
11 2
FF
FF
2 0
22 0
2 0
=F
X
(3)








02 2
=F
Since this equality holds for any
2222
O=,,
X
F and any
22
, some may want to regard the 0
as the state
after the measurement




01111
MO:=,,,
C
X
FS
in
the (H). Thus, in spite of the (F2), the (H) may be al-
C
opyright © 2011 SciRes. JQIS
39
S. ISHIKAWA
lowed in classical cases if the 0
may be regarded as
something represented by the term such as “imaginary
state” (cf. [5]). This is the meaning of the informal (H).
Example 4 [How to use Rule 2 (Causality)] Consider a
tree

01
:=, ,,,
n
Ttt t with the root . This is also
characterized by the map
0
t

0
π:Tt T such that


π=max <tsTst. Let

:
tt

2
,,
tttT
t


be a Markov relation, which is also represented by

 

0
π,π
:t
ttttTt
 . Let an observable O: =
t

,,
ttt
X
F
*
0
pt
S
in the be given for each . And let
. Consider “measurements” such as
t
T
tT
0
(J) for each , take a measurement of an observ-
able for the system with a “moving state”
t
Ot
 




0
** *
0π,π
;:
mm
t
tt ttT t


SS
,
where the meaning of “moving state” is not clear yet.
Recalling that the (F3) says that a state never moves, we
consider the meaning of the (J) as follows: For each
s
T, put
=
s
TtTts
. And define the observable
O=
, ,
s
stT t tT t
ss
X
F

 in
(due to Heisenberg
picture) as follows:






1π,
π
Oifπ
O=O(O) ifsπ
s
s
t
stt
ts
TT
T


s
(6)
if the commutativity condition holds (i.e., if the simulta-
neous observable exists) for




1
ππ,
OO
t
ststt

each

π
s
T. Using (6) iteratively, we can finally
obtain the observable
0
t in0
t Thus the above (J) is O
represented by the measurement . This
also satisfies the (F2).

00
0[]
MO,
t
tS
Remark 6 [Kolmogorov extension theorem] In the
general cases such that countable additivity and infinite
(in Remarks 1 and 3) are required, the existence of
the above
T
0
Ot is, by using the Kolmogorov extension
theorem in probability theory [9], proved in the -
algebraic formulation (cf. [4,5] and Appendix later). We
think that this fact is evidence that the interpretation (F2)
is hidden behind the utility of the Kolmogorov extension
theorem. Recall the following well-known statement that
always appears in the beginning of probability theory:
*
W
(K) Let

,,
X
P

P
be a probability space. Then, the
probability that an event occurs is given
by ,

which, as well as Rule 1, is a statement without reality.
We consider that the Kolmogorov extension theorem is
regarded as one of the finest answers to the problem:
How should the statement (K) be used? That is, in
mathematical probability theory, the answer is presented
as the form of a basic theorem (i.e., the Kolmogorov ex-
tension theorem). On the other hand, in measurement
theory, the problem (D) is answered by the interpretation
(F).
Remark 7 [Wavefunction collapse] Again reconsider
the (J) in the simplest case that

011 0
=,, π=Tttt t

,S
.
Taking a measurement t, we know that
the measured value belongs to . Then, it may

00
0
MO
t

0
0t
be usual to consider that a certain wavefunction collapse
happens by the measurement, that is,
*pt
S
0
0
*
0
00 .
pt

S And continuously, we take a mea-
surement 011
00
0
,
MO,
tt t
tS



. Here, the probability
that a measured value belongs to is, by Rule 1,
given by
1
1t


0
01
0,11
.
tt
F
 However, this
must be equal to the conditional


01
0,11tt
F
0
probability



001
001
F
FX


if the commutativity condition holds (i.e., the simultane-
ous observable

00011
0101 0011
,
,
O=O O
=,,:=
ttttt
tttt tttt
X
XFF

 F
exists). This implies that it suffices to consider only the
measurement

0011
0
0,
MO O,
At ttt
tS

. That is, two
measurements
00
0
MO,
t
tS

and
01 10
00
,
MO,
tt t
tS






are not needed. Also, if the commutativity condition is
ignored in the argument of the wavefunction collapse, it
is doubtful.
Example 5 [Bell’s inequality] According to [11], we
shall study the following steps [1-3] in measurement
theory.
[Step 1]: Put
=1,1X. Let 12
=1a

 and
12
=1b

be complex numbers such that a
22
12
=1

and 22
12
=1b

 . Consider
a probability space
22
,,
ab
XX
such that








1122
112 2
1,1 =1,1 =14
1,1=1,1= 14.
ab ab
ab ab
 
 
 

Define and calculate the correlation function
,Pab
such that
Copyright © 2011 SciRes. JQIS
40 S. ISHIKAWA
 
12
12121122
(,)
,,=
ab
xx XX
Pabxxx x
 

 
(7)
Our problem is as follows.
(L) Find a measurement
in a C*-algebra
such that



0
22
MO:= ,, ,
ab ab
XXFS
 

0
=
ab ab
F



2.PX
This will be answered in the following step [2].
[Step: 2]. In what follows, we shall investigate the (L)
in two cases (i.e., quantum case
22
=B


2
.
and
classical case ).

0
=C


1): Quantum case
[ (
cf. [10,11])]
  
222
==BBB
P
ut

2
12
10
=,=
01
ee

 

For each , define the observables

,cab

O,,
cc
X
XG
in such that
2
B




11
11
1,1
11
22
cc
cc
GG
cc
 

 
 
.
Further consider the quantum system composed of two
particles formulated in Put

22
.B =
s
ss

and

*
22
000
=,
pB





S where =
s

1221 2eeee and 01
=ee
1

22
. Consider the
unitary operator
UB such that
0=.
s
U
Define the observable

22
O,,
ab ab
XXF:=

*ab
UG GU
in Thus we get a measurement
22
.B



22 0
MO,
ab
BS
 in .

22
B
This clearly satisfies the (L) since we easily calculate that,
for each

2
12
,
x
xX,















012
0120
12
12
,
=, ,
=,
=,.
ab
ab
s
ab
ab
Fxx
Fxx
Gx Gx
xx

2): Classical case [
 
000
==AC C C ]
Let
0
00
=,


, and put 00
=

*
0
(
pCS,
And define the observable


22
O:= ,,
ab ab
X
XF in
0
C
 such that





12 012
,=,
ab ab
Fxx xx


 .
Thus we get a measurement

00
MO,
ab
CS




,
which clearly satisfies the (L).
[Step: 3]. For each , let
=1,2k

12
=1
kkk
a

and
1
12
=
kkk
b

be complex numbers such that
==
kk
ab1
. Further, consider the parallel measure-
ment ,=1,2ij


0
22
MO :=,,,
ij j
i
ab ab
XXFS
in
the tensor -algebra
*
C,=1,2ij
, by which the meas-
ured value
8
x
X is obtained as follows:
 
11 1112 1221212222
12121212
2
,=1,2
=,,,,,,,
ij
xxxxxxxxx
X
Here, the (7) says that, for each ,
,=1,2ij




12
120 12
,
11 22
,= ,
=
ij
ij ij
ijijijij ij
ab
xx XX
ij ij
PabxxFx x
 


Thus, putting
11 22
11 11
=1,= ,=1,=
22
abab ,

we calculate that
 
1112212 2
,,, ,=PabPabPa bPa b 22(8)
Therefore, we can conclude that
(M) Bell’s inequality (i.e., a certain inequality such as
“the left-hand side of (8)”, (cf. [10,11])) is
broken in classical systems as well as in quantum
systems.
2
s

This may be somewhat significant since it says that the
non-commutativity of
2
B is not necessarily indis-
pensable for the (8). Although the above discussion in
the steps [1-3] is easy and similar to that of [11], it
should be noted that we can not assert the (M) if we do
not have measurement theory (particularly, classical
measurement theory ) with the interpretation (F).
C
opyright © 2011 SciRes. JQIS
S. ISHIKAWA
Copyright © 2011 SciRes. JQIS
41
5. Conclusions
Since we advanced from quantum mechanics (i.e., the
mathematical formulation of Heisenberg’s uncertainty
principle; [12]) to classical measurement theory, at first
we had no way except relying on so-called Copenhagen
interpretation in our investigations. That is, we investi-
gated classical measurement theory [2-6] without the
clear answer to the problem:
(N) What is the Copenhagen interpretation? What is
“interpretation”? Or, how should Rules 1 and 2 be
used?
However, in this paper we assert that we can master
measurement theory thanks to man’s linguistic compe-
tence if we know the interpretation (F), which may be
characterized as the essence extracted from various ideas
in so-called Copenhagen interpretation.
Although N. Bohr said, in the Bohr-Einstein debates
[13,14], that the interpretation of a physical theory has to
rely on an experimental practice, we consider that the
reality should be abandoned if we hope that measurement
theory includes classical measurements. In this sense, we
agree with A. Einstein, who never accepted the Copenha-
gen interpretation as physics. That is, in spite of Bohr’s
realistic view, we propose the following linguistic view:
(O) In the beginning was the language called meas-
urement theory (with the interpretation (F)). And,
for example, quantum mechanics can be fortu-
nately described in this language. And moreover,
almost all scientists have already mastered this
language partially and informally since statistics (at
least, its basic part) is characterized as one of as-
pects of measurement theory (cf. [2-6]).
If it is so, measurement theory may be a miraculous
language, which is common in almost all fields of sci-
ence. We want to consider that this miracle was origi-
nally discovered by J. von Neumann in his famous book
[1]. That is because we think that measurement theory
(with the interpretation (F)) is the necessary consequence
of his Hilbert space formulation.
Although we believe that the interpretation (F) is the
unique answer to the problem (D), this should be of
course examined seriously. Thus, we hope that our pro-
posal (F), which is the common interpretation of classi-
cal and quantum systems, will be discussed from various
viewpoints.
6. Acknowledgements
The author wishes to acknowledge Prof. S. Koizumi in
Keio University for valuable suggestions.
7. References
[1] J. von Neumann, “Mathematical Foundations of Quantum
Mechanics,” Springer Verlag, Berlin, 1932.
[2] S. Ishikawa, “A Quantum Mechanical Approach to Fuzzy
Theory,” Fuzzy Sets and Systems, Vol. 90, No. 3, 1997,
pp. 277-306. doi:10.1016/S0165-0114(96)00114-5
[3] S. Ishikawa, “Statistics in Measurements,” Fuzzy Sets and
Systems, Vol. 116, No. 2, 2000, pp. 141-154.
doi:10.1016/S0165-0114(98)00280-2
[4] S. Ishikawa, “Mathematical Foundations of Measurement
Theory,” Keio University Press Inc., 2006, 335 Pages.
http://www.keio-up.co.jp/kup/mfomt/).
[5] S. Ishikawa, “A New Formulation of Measurement The-
ory,” Far East Journal of Dynamical Systems, Vol. 10,
No. 1, 2008, pp. 107-117.
[6] K. Kikuchi, S. Ishikawa, “Psychological tests in meas-
urement theory,” Far East Journal of Theoretical Statis-
tics, Vol. 32, No. 1, 2010, pp. 81-99.
[7] S. Sakai, “C*-Algebras and W*-Algebras,” Ergebnisse der
Mathematik und ihrer Grenzgebiete (Band 60), Springer-
Verlag, Berlin, 1971.
[8] E. B. Davies, “Quantum Theory of Open Systems,” Aca-
demic Press, Cambridge, 1976.
[9] A. Kolmogorov, “Foundations of the Theory of Probabil-
ity (Translation),” Chelsea Publishing Co., New York,
1950.
[10] J. S. Bell, “On the Einstein-Podolosky-Rosen Paradox,”
Physics, Vol. 1, 1966, pp. 195-200.
[11] F. Selleri, “Die Debatte um die Quantentheorie,” Friedr.
Vieweg & Sohn Verlagsgesellscvhaft MBH, Braun-
schweig, 1983.
[12] S. Ishikawa, “Uncertainty Relation in Simultaneous
Measurements for Arbitrary Observables,” Reports on
Mathematical Physics, Vol. 9, 1991, pp. 257-273.
doi:10.1016/0034-4877(91)90046-P
[13] A. Einstein, B. Podolosky and N. Rosen, “Can Quan-
tum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Con-
sidered Complete?” Physical Review, Vol. 47, No. 10,
1935, pp. 777-780. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.47.777
[14] N. Bohr, “Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of
Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?” Physical Re-
view, Vol. 48, 1935, pp. 696-702.
doi:10.1103/PhysRev.48.696
42 S. ISHIKAWA
Appendix: W*-algebraic formulation
The C*-algebraic formulation (mentioned in this paper)
is fundamental and essential in measurement theory.
However, as mentioned in Remarks 1 and 3, the
W*-algebraic formulation (cf. [5]) is, from the mathe-
matical point of view, more handy than the C*-algebraic
formulation (just like the Lebesgue integral is more
handy than the Riemann integral). Thus we think that
each of two formulations has its merits and demerits. In
what follows, according to [5], in which there is a part
that should be corrected, we shall add the W*-algebraic
formulation.
Consider the pair

,
B
H

, called a basic structure.
Here, is a C*-algebra, and



BH
 
is a particular C*-algebra (called a W*-algebra)
such that
BH
is the weak closure of in
BH. Let
*
be the pre-dual Banach space, whose existence is
assured (cf. [7]).
For example, we see (cf. [7]) that, when
=c
BH,
1) “trace class”,
*=

=BH, *= “trace
class”.
Also, when ,

0
=C
2) “the space of all signed measures on
*=
”,
 


2
=, ,LBL

 ,
=,
1
*L
,
where
is some measure on (cf. [7]).
For instance, in the above 2) we must clarify the
meaning of the “value” of

0
F
for
,FL

and 0


*
. This is easily done as follows. Let
be as in (2). An element
p
S

F

*p
is said to
be essentially continuous at 0, if there
uniquely exists a complex number
S
such that
(*) if

,=

1
converges to
*
0
p
S
*
(i.e
in the sense of weak* topology of .,
 
0
GG



G ), then
F
converges to
.
And the value of

0
F
is defined by the
.
An observable

,O:= ,
X
F in is defined as
follows:
1) [
-field]
X
is a set,

X
 , the power set
of X) is a
-field of X, that is, “
12
,, F 
=1nn
F
”, “
F
XF ”.
2) [Countable additivity] F is a mapping from to
satisfying: a): for every , 
F
is a
non-negative element in such that

0
F
I , b):
=0F and
F
XI
, where 0 and I is the 0-ele-
ment and the identity in respectively. c): for any
countable decomposition of

12
,,,
n
,
(i.e.,
, ,

1, 2,3,,n=n =1
=
nn
 =
ij
 
ij
), it holds that


=1 n
n
FF
in the sense
of weak* topology in .
Now we can present Rule 1 in the W*-algebraic for-
mulation as follows.
Rule 1' [Measurement] The probability that a meas-
ured value
x
X obtained by the measurement


0
,S
MO:= ,,XF
belongs to a set
 is
given by
0F
if
F is essentially co ntinuo us
at
*
0
p
S.
Next, we explain Rule 2. Let

1
1,
B
H and
1


2
2
2,BH


 be basic structures. A continuous linear
operator 2
1,2 : (with weak* topology) 1
(with
weak* topology) is called a Markov operator, if it satis-
fies that 1):
1,2 2
F0
for any non-negative element
2
F
in 2
, 2):
=
1,2 21
I
I, where k
I
is the identity
in k
,
2=1,k. Here note that, for any observable
22
O:=, ,
X
F in 2
, the

1,2 2
,,
X
F is an
observable in 1
.
Remark 8 In addition to the above 1) and 2), it may be
natural to assume that
1,2 21
 and

1,22222 2
1
supsuchthat1= 1FF F 
.
However, from the mathematical point of view, this as-
sumption is not necessarily needed.
Let
,T
be a tree, i.e., a partial ordered set such
that “13
tt
and 23
tt
” implies “1 or
21
tt2
tt
”.
Here, note that T is not necessarily finite.
Assume the completeness of the ordered set T. That is,
for any subset
TT
bounded from below (i.e., there
exists
Tt
such that
tt
tT

T
TttT


), there
uniquely exists an element satisfying the
following conditions, 1): , 2): if

T
inf

inf
s
ttT
, then

inf
s
T
.
Definition 1' [Markov relation] The family

21 2
12 12
,,
:tt
tt tt T
 is called a Markov relation
(due to the Heisenberg picture), if it satisfies the follow-
ing conditions 1) and 2).
1) With each tT
, a basic structure

,
t
t
t
B
H



is associated.
2) For every
2
12
,tt T
, a Markov operator 12
,:
tt
2
t

1
t
is defined. And it satisfies that
12 23
,,tt tt

13
,
=tt
holds for any
12
,tt, .

2
23
,ttT
Now Rule 2 is presented as follows:
Rule 2' [Causality] The causality is represented by a
Markov relation

21 2
12 12
,,
:tt
tt tt T
 .
C
opyright © 2011 SciRes. JQIS