Open Journal of Discrete Mathematics
Vol.07 No.01(2017), Article ID:73747,19 pages
10.4236/ojdm.2017.71004
On the 2-Domination Number of Complete Grid Graphs
Ramy Shaheen, Suhail Mahfud, Khames Almanea
Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Science, Tishreen University, Lattakia, Syria
Copyright © 2017 by authors and Scientific Research Publishing Inc.
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution International License (CC BY 4.0).
http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/
Received: November 22, 2016; Accepted: January 20, 2017; Published: January 23, 2017
ABSTRACT
A set D of vertices of a graph G = (V, E) is called k-dominating if every vertex
is adjacent to some k vertices of D. The k-domination number of a graph G,
, is the order of a smallest k-dominating set of G. In this paper we calculate the k-domination number (for k = 2) of the product of two paths Pm × Pn for m = 1, 2, 3, 4, 5 and arbitrary n. These results were shown an error in the paper [1] .
Keywords:
k-Dominating Set, k-Domination Number, 2-Dominating Set, 2-Domination Number, Cartesian Product Graphs, Paths
1. Introduction
Let
be a graph. A subset of vertices
is called a 2-dominating set of G if for every
, either
or v is adjacent to at least two vertices of D. The 2-domination number
is equal to
.
The Cartesian product G ´ H of two graphs G and H is the graph with vertex set
, where two vertices
,
are adjacent if and only if either
and
or
and
.
Let G be a path of order n with vertex set
. Then for two paths of order m and n respectively, we have
. The jth column of
is
. If D is a 2-dominating set for
, then we put
. Let
. The sequence
is called a 2-dominating sequence corresponding to D. For a graph G, we refer to minimum and maximum degrees by #Math_25# and
, and for simplicity denoted those by δ and Δ, respectively. Also, we denote by
and
to order and size of graph G, respectively.
2. Notation and Terminology
Fink and Jacobson [2] [3] in 1985 to introduced the concept of multiple domination. A subset
is k-dominating in G if every vertex of
has at least k neighbors in D. The cardinality of a minimum k-dominating set is called the k-domination number
of G. Clearly,
. Naturally, every k-dominating set of a graph G contains all vertices of degree less than k. Of course, every
-dominating set is also a k-dominating set and so
. Moreover, the vertex set V is the only
-dominating set but evidently it is not a minimum D-dominating set. Thus every graph G satisfies
.
For a comprehensive treatment of domination in graphs, see the monographs by Haynes et al. [4] . Also, for more information see [5] [6] . Fink and Jacobson [2] , introduced the following theorems:
Theorem 2.1 [2] . If
, is an integer and G is a graph with
, then
.
Theorem 2.2 [2] . If T is a tree, then
.
In [6] , Hansberg and Volkmann, proved the following theorem.
Theorem 2.4 [6] . Let
be a graph of order n and minimum degree δ and
let
. If
, then
.
Cockayne, et al. [7] , established an upper bound for the k-domination number of a graph G has minimum degree k, they gave the following result.
Theorem 2.3 [7] . Let G be a graph with minimum degree at least k, then
.
Blidia, et al. [8] , studied the k-domination number. They introduced the following results.
Theorem 2.5 [8] . Let G be a bipartite graph and S is the set of all vertices of degree at
most
, then
.
Favaron, et al. [9] , gave new upper bounds of
.
Corollary 2.6 [9] . Let G be a graph of order n and minimum degree δ. If
is
an integer, then
In [4] , Haynes et al. showed that the 2-domination number is bounded from below by the total domination number for every nontrivial tree.
Theorem 2.7 [4] . For every nontrivial tree,
.
Also, Volkmann [10] gave the important following result.
Theorem 2.8 [10] . Let G be a graph with minimum degree
, then
Shaheen [11] considered the 2-domination number of Toroidal grid graphs and gave an upper and lower bounds. Also, in [12] , he introduced the following results.
Theorem 2.9 [12] .
1)
.
2)
,
.
3)
,
.
4)
.
5)
,
.
6)
,
,
.
In this paper we calculate the k-domination number (for k = 2) of the product of two paths
for m = 1, 2, 3, 4, 5 and arbitrary n. These results were shown an error in the paper [1] . We believe that these results were wrong. In our paper we will provide improved and corrected her, especially for m = 3, 4, 5.
The following formulas appeared in [1] ,
In this paper, we correct the results in [1] and proves the following:
3. Main Results
Our main results here are to establish the domination number of Cartesian product of two paths
and
for m = 1, 2, 3, 4, 5 and arbitrary n. We study 2-dominating sets in complete grid graphs using one technique: by given a minimum of upper 2-dominating set D of
and then we establish that D is a minimum 2-domi- nating set of
for several values of m and arbitrary n. Definitely we have
.
Let G be a path of order n with vertex set
. For two paths of order m and n respectively is:
. The jth column
is
.
If D is a 2-dominating set for
then we put
. Let
. The sequence
is called a 2-dominating sequence corresponding to D. Always we have
. Suppose that
for some j (where j ¹ 1 or n). The vertices of the jth column can only be 2-dominated by vertices of the (j − 1)st columns and (j + 1)st columns. Thus we have
, then
. In general
.
Notice 3.1.
1) The study of 2-dominating sequence
is the same as the study of the 2-dominating sequence
.
2) If subsequence
is not possible, then its reverse
is not possible.
3) We say that two subsequences
are equivalent, if the sequence
is possible.
We need the useful following lemma.
Lemma 3.1. There is a minimum 2-dominating set for
with 2-dominating sequence
such that, for all
, is
.
Proof. Let D be a minimum 2-dominating set for
with 2-dominating sequence
. Assume that for some j, sj is large. Then we modify D by moving two vertices from column j, one to column j − 1 and another one to column j + 1, such that the resulting set is still 2-dominating set for
. For
and
, let
. If
, then we define
, see Figure 1. We repeat this process if necessary eventually leads to a 2-dominating set with required properties. Also, we get D1 is a 2-dominating set for
with
. Thus, we can assume that every four consecutive vertices of the jth column include at most three vertices of D. This implies that
, for all 1 ≤ j ≤ n.
To prove the lower bound, we suppose that
is be a maximum, i.e.,
. Then for each
, we have
. When
, there at must
vertices does not in
. This implies that
. So, the same as for
. □
By Lemma 3.1, always we have a minimum 2-dominating set D with 2-dominating sequence
, such that
, for all
.
Lemma 3.2.
.
Proof. Let
.
We have D is a 2-dominating set of Pn for
with
, also
is a 2-dominating set of Pn for
with
.
Let D1 be a minimum 2-dominating set for Pn with
. Since
, we need to
, also if
then
are belong to D1,
this implies that
for
. Thus implies that
. We result that
. □
Theorem 3.1.
.
Proof. Let a set
.
It is clear that
. (1)
We can check that D is 2-dominating set for
, see Figure 2. Let D1 be a minimum 2-dominating set for
with dominating sequence
. If
for all
, then
. (2)
Let
for some j, then
, also we have
and
. Now we define a new sequence
, (not necessarily a 2-dominating sequence) as follows:
For
, if
or n, we put
,
and
.
If
or n, we put
,
and
.
Otherwise
.
We get a sequence
have property that each
with
. (3)
By (1), (2) and (3) is
. This completes the proof of the theorem. □
Theorem 3.2.
.
Proof. Let
.
Figure 2. A 2-dominating set for P2 × P10.
.
We have
and
. (4)
By definition D and
we note that
D is 2-dominating set for
when
, (see Figure 3, for P3 × P14).
is 2-dominating set for
when
, (see Figure 4, for P3 × P10).
Let D1 be a minimum 2-dominating set for
with 2-dominating sequence
we have
and
if
then
,
if
then
.
Also for
, if
then
then
then
If no one of
for all j, then
. (5)
Let
(
or n) for some j, we define a sequence
, (not necessarily a 2-dominating sequence ) as follows:
If
, then we put
,
and
, otherwise
. We have
. We note that the sequence
have the
property if
then
. Thus implies that
. (6)
From (4), (5) and (6) we get the required result. □
Theorem 3.3.
Figure 3. A 2-dominating set for P3 × P14.
Figure 4. A 2-dominating set for P3 × P10.
Proof. Let a set D defined as follows:
.
We can check that the following sets are 2-dominating set for
(see Figure 5, for
) as indicated:
D is 2-dominating set for
when
.
is 2-dominating set for
when
.
is 2-dominating set for
when
.
We have
Let D1 be a minimum 2-dominating set for
with 2-dominating sequence
we shall show that
By Lemma 3.1, we have
. Thus
If
then
.
If
then
.
If
then
.
Also, we have
. If
then
, and if
then
Figure 5. A 2-dominating set for P4 × P11.
.
We define a new set
with sequence
, (not necessarily a 2-dominating
sequence) as follows: if
, let
. Now, for
to
, if
, then we put
,
and
Thus, for
, we have
. Since if
then
and if
, then
this implies that
, which implies that
We have three cases:
Case 1:
, then
, these implies that
and
also
.
Case 2:
then
. Thus implies that
and
Then
Case 3:
and
and
. Two cases are similar by symmetry. We consider the first case:
and
, this implies that
and
But, we have the 2-domination number is positive integer number, also we have
for
,
Thus implies that
Finally, we get
This complete the proof of the theorem. □
Theorem 3.4.
Proof. Let a set D defined as follows:
We can check that the following sets are 2-dominating set for
(see Figure 6, for
) as indicated:
We have
and
This complete the proof of the theorem. □
Lemma 3.3. The following cases are not possible:
1) (1, 2, 3, 1).
2) (1, 2, 1).
3) (1, 4, 1, 1).
Figure 6. A 2-dominating set for P5 × P23.
4) (1, 3, 1, 3, 1, 3).
5) (2, 1, 3).
6) (2, 2, 2, 2, 2, 2).
Proof. It follows directly from the drawing.
Lemma 3.4.
1) There is one case for subsequence
.
2) There is one case for subsequence
.
3) There is one case for subsequence
.
4) There is one case for subsequence
.
Proof. It follows directly from the drawing (see Figure 7).
Lemma 3.5.
1)
.
2)
.
3)
.
4) If
then
.
5) If
then
.
Proof. 1) By Lemma 3.3, imply that
.
2) By 1, we have
. If
, then we have the cases
.
From Lemma 3.3, we have
, this implies that
.
If
then
. This implies that
.
3) We have
and
. If
, then there is one case
(where the cases
are not possible). But the
case
is not compatible with any of the cases when
, this implies that
Figure 7. Cases 1, 2, 3 and 4 of Lemma 3.4.
. Then
(where the case
is not possible). If
then
.
4) We have
, then from 2 is
.
5) We have
, then from 2 is
. This complete the proof of the Lemma. □
Lemma 3.6. If
, then
or
.
Proof. We suppose the contrary
. From Lemma 3.5,
, else
. Now, we must study the case
. We have
, by Lem-
ma 3.3, the case
is not possible, this implies that not all elements of the subsequence
are equal to the value 2. If
where at least one of them is equal or greater than 3, then
, this is a contradiction with
. Now, we have
, where one of the subsequence ele-
ment
is at most equal the value 1 (where
). We consider the cases
for
:
1)
or
(where two cases are similar), we study the case
then
, these implies that
. By Lemma 3.5, we have
then
, this is a contradiction.
2)
or
(where two cases are similar), we study the case
then
, (because the case
is not possible). If
then
and we have
then
(because two cases
are not possible). Thus implies that
, this is a contradiction.
3)
, then we have two subcases results from
:
Subcase 1:
then
(because two cases
and
are not possible). Thus implies
that
, this is a contradiction.
Subcase 2: If
or conversely (two cases are similar in studying), so
we will study case
then
if
, then
, because
, we have
. Then
, this is a contradiction).
If
, then
. We have
. This implies that
this is a contradiction.
Finally, we get if
, then
or
. This completely the proof. □
Result 3.1. If
, then from Lemma 3.6, we have the cases for subsequence
:
It is 15 cases (where
with
). We have three cases with
,
and
.
Case 1:
(including the cases
or
). We have these cases are
and comes before these cases,
or comes after these cases
, i.e., if
then
and if
then
.
Case 2:
and these are the 8 remaining cases. We will study these cases after rejecting isomorphism cases when there is two cases or more, where
, then we will study only one case. We have 8 cases as follows:
We note that two cases
are similar where one of them is contrary to the other one, so we study the case
. Also, two cases
are similar, so we study the case
. Then we study these cases:
. □
Notice 3.2. We note that all the possible cases in Result 3.1, do not begin or end with 3 or 4 and it do not begin or end with
or
such that
or
, and
or
. Thus implies that if
,
then
. Also, we note cases
are beginning with (1, 3, 1, 3), but from
Lemma 3.4, we get
. Now, remains our three cases for studying by the following lemma are:
□
Result 3.2. If
where
or
then
, also for
or
because it are similar to two cases
or
, respectively. □
Lemma 3.7. If
, such that
, then
. Furthermore, if
then
.
Proof. By Result 3.2, if
,
,
or
then
. From Lemma 3.5, we
get
. Assume
then we have two cases for
:
Case 1.
. Then
, by lemma 3.5,
.
Case 2.
or
and both cases are similar, so we will consider
the first case. We have
then by Lemma 3.5,
. If
then
. Assume
, if
the proof is finish. Assume
then we have cases
.
Subcase 2.1. If
then
. This implies that
{By Lemma 3.5,
}.
Subcase 2.2. If
then
. If
then
. Assume that
then we have only one case
or
. For any case we have
. So, we get
. Which implies that
.
Subcase 2.3. If
then
{because the case
is not possible, by Lemma 3.3}. Then
.
Subcase 2.4. If
then
, we have the following cases:
2.4.1.
then
.
2.4.2.
{because there is only one case for
such that
But according to distribution vertices
and
we have
.
2.4.3.
then
. This implies that
. We will study the cases that leads to
, i.e.,
, {because the cases which leads to
the proof will be done}. Now,
we have the fixed case
We will consider the vertices
which imply the following:
2.4.3.1. If
then
this implies that
and
is not possible.
2.4.3.2. If
then
and
which imply
that
or (1, 3, 1), and the only possible case is (1, 3, 1). Thus implies that
. By Lemma 3.4 and
Lemma 3.5 is
, these implies that
.
2.4.3.3. If
then
, i.e.,
. We have
{because the case
is not possible}. Then we have the following cases for
:
1). If
then
and
, but the case
is not possible.
2). If
and
then
, also the case
is not possible.
3). If
,
and
then
which
gets
and
.
4). If
and
then
, but the case
is not possible. If
,
and
then we gets
During the proof of Lemma, we notice that if
and
, then
. This complete the proof. □
Result 3.3. Based on the Lemma 3.6, and the other Lemmas and results precede it.
We see that when we have case of
, then the only case that comes after it, is
such that
which continues in the same
way or it is followed by 7 columns contain 16 vertices from S {by Lemma 3.6,
, because
,
}. When this case is repeated then
and then when the case
it is necessary, the case
exists as well {where
} these implies that
then
. □
Lemma 3.8. Let S be 2-dominating set for
then:
1)
.
2) If
then
(
then
).
3)
.
4)
.
5)
and if
then
, also if
then
6)
.
7)
.
8) If
then either
or
, also if
then either
or
.
Proof. The study of dominating sequence
is the same as the study of the dominating sequence
, so we study one case
. Also, the
study of
is the same as the study of
.
1) We have
, if
then
thus,
if
then
these implies that
.
2) If
, then we have only one the case
these implies that
and
then
.
3) If
, then
{because
} and if
then by 2, is
.
4) If
then
these implies that
and if
then
{because
}. Assume that
, then we have three cases:
4.1)
then
, because the case
is not possible. Also the case
is not possible, else when
and this is not possible.
4.2)
then
because the cases
,
are not possible.
4.3)
then
, because the cases
,
are not possible. Thus implies that we have
.
5) By Lemma 3.4, we have two cases for
and these two cases are
, furthermore these cannot be shown here because
. Thus
implies that we
.
6). If
then
.
(where by Lemma 3.5, we have
). Let
then
these implies that
. Thus implies that
{because
}.
7) If
then from Lemma 3.5,
. Let
{because
} then
. This implies that
{by Notice 3.2}.
8) If
then either
or
. We have
, then
we have three
cases:
8.1)
, then
because the cases
are not possible.
Thus implies that
.
8.2)
, then
and if
then
. By Lemma 3.4,
. Thus implies that
.
8.3)
, then
it has minimal numerals in the following cases
and for the case
is not compatible with the case
Thus implies that
. This completes the proof. □
Theorem 3.5.
Proof. By Result 3.3, we have
. By Theorem 3.4, we get
Now, for
, by Theorem 3.4, we have
. From Result 3.3, we have
. We will study the cases:
1)
. We have
. So, we consider the following:
a)
then
and by Lemma 3.8,
b)
if
then
Let
then by Lemma 3.8,
or
. If
then
{where the case
is the same as
}. If
then by Lemma 3.8, we have
And with Theorem 3.4, we get
.
2) When
we have two cases:
a)
. Thus implies that
then
b)
{where
} then
Then by Theorem 3.4, we get
.
3)
. We have two cases:
a) If
then
. Thus implies that
b) If
then
. Thus implies that
By Theorem 3.4, we get
Finally, we get
This completes the proof. □
Cite this paper
Shaheen, R., Mah- fud, S. and Almanea, K. (2017) On the 2-Domination Number of Complete Grid Graphs. Open Journal of Discrete Mathematics, 7, 32-50. http://dx.doi.org/10.4236/ojdm.2017.71004
References
- 1. Mohan, J.J. and Kelkar, I. (2012) Restrained 2-Domination Number of Complete Grid Graphs. International Journal of Applied Mathematics and Computation, 4, 352-358.
- 2. Fink, J.F. and Jacobson, M.S. (1985) n-Domination in graphs, in: Graph Theory with Application to Algorithms and Computer Science. John Wiley and Sons, New York, 282-300.
- 3. Fink, J.F. and Jacobson, M.S. (1985) On n-Domination, n-Dependence and Forbidden Subgraphs. In: Graph Theory with Application to Algorithms and Computer Science, John Wiley and Sons, New York, 301-311.
- 4. Haynes, T.W., Hedetniemi, S.T., Henning, M.A. and Slater, P.J. (2003) H-Forming Sets in Graphs. Discrete Mathematics, 262, 159-169. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0012-365X(02)00496-X
- 5. Haynes, T.W., Hedetniemi, S.T. and Slater, P.J. (1998) Fundamentals of Domination in Graphs. Marcel Dekker, Inc., New York.
- 6. Hansberg, A. and Volkmann, L. (2009) Upper Bounds on the k-Domination Number and the k-Roman Domination Number. Discrete Applied Mathematics, 157, 1634-1639. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.dam.2008.10.011
- 7. Cockayne, E.J., Gamble, B. and Shepherd, B. (1985) An Upper Bound for the k-Domination Number of a Graph. Journal of Graph Theory, 9, 533-534. https://doi.org/10.1002/jgt.3190090414
- 8. Blidia, M., Chellali, M. and Volkmann, L. (2006) Some Bounds on the p-Domination Number in Trees. Discrete Mathematics, 306, 2031-2037. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.disc.2006.04.010
- 9. Favaron, O., Hansberg, A. and Volkmann, L. (2008) On k-Domination and Minimum Degree in Graphs. Journal of Graph Theory, 57, 33-40. https://doi.org/10.1002/jgt.20279
- 10. Volkmann, L. (2010) A Bound on the k-Domination Number of a Graph. Czechoslovak Mathematical Journal, 60, 77-83. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10587-010-0019-1
- 11. Shaheen, R. (2009) Bounds for the 2-Domination Number of Toroidal Grid Graphs. International Journal of Computer Mathematics, 86, 584-588. https://doi.org/10.1080/00207160701690284
- 12. Shaheen, R. (2013) On the 2-Domination Number of Cartesian Product of Two Cycles. Advances and Applications in Discrete Mathematics, 12, 83-108.