F. CHANG
determinism is impossible. According to Popper, “scientific”
determinism is a doctrine that if we were given a sufficiently
precise description of events, together with all the laws of na-
ture, any events could be rationally predicted, with any desired
degree of precision. Popper firmly opposed to scientific deter-
minism. In his opinion, the future predictions of a certain mo-
ment would be possible only in a completely isolated, steady
and periodic system. But it is very rare in nature, and certainly
didn’t exist in the modern society. In natural science, the idea
of a law which determined the direction and the character of
evolution was “a typical nineteenth century mistake, arising out
of the general tendency to ascribe to the ‘Natural Law’ the
functions traditionally ascribed to God”; In social science, “so-
ciety is changing, developing”, and “this development is not, in
the main, repetitive” (Popper, 1962: p. 340). So Scientific Mar-
xism established its historicism on the “scientific” determinism,
which was certainly not scientific.
Besides opposing to Scientific Marxism, Popper also at-
tacked Marx directly. Why attacked Marx, then? It because that
Marx was “a false prophet”, especially, Marx “misled scores of
intelligent people into believing that historical prophecy is the
scientific way of approaching social problems” (Popper, 1947:
p. 78). So here, another vital historical question emerged: was
Marx the historical prophet described by Popper?
Sincerely, historicism was indeed an important tradition of
Western culture. Ancient Greek philosophy, medieval theology,
French positivism, English empiricism, Kant and Hegel, though
these schools were very different, all of them believed: behind
the changing world, there were so-called eternal laws or pri-
mary beings. In any case, the world was determined by these
laws, to discover them and forecast the future of the world was
the primary task of scientific cognitions. According to Russo,
this characteristic of Western culture came from the anxiety of
people to get “safety”. In this sense, Religion assured to people
the “eternal” and thus provided a “decisive” future, which gave
the spiritual comfort to them. Science, like philosophy, also
aimed to find some permanent substratum amid changing phe-
nomena (Russo, 1961: pp. 45-46). However, in fact, precisely
in Marx this tenden c y had b ee n curbed and eve n abandoned .
We have indicated above that Marx found a perspective of
dynamic social practice when he overcame the mechanical
materialism of Feuerbach, and found a “historical” perspective
when he critiqued Hegel’s speculative idealism. Consequently,
Marx suggested a significant meaning when he wrote down
“We know only a single science, the science of history.”
(Marx/Engels, 1975: p. 28). “The science of history” was a
science about movements or changes, namely, both social sci-
ence and natural science should understand the world in the
perspective of changes. How can there be eternal things! As
long as viewing science alongside social practice (the main
characteristics of social practice are subjectivity, activity and
change), meanwhile, understanding science in the point of dia-
lectics (dialectics “regards every historically developed social
form as in fluid movement, and therefore takes into account its
transient nature not less than its momentary existence.” (Karl
Marx, 1982: p. 20). Marx’s understanding of science should not
be regarded as determinism, and historical prophecy certainly
should not be treated as Marx’s scientific method and goal.
Actually, Marx valued the general laws of human history
only within certain limits. General laws were not Marx’s scien-
tific goals. For example, at the beginning of political economy
research, Marx pointed that the modern science apart from the
changing social practice, but seeking of the general laws. Marx
said: “What indeed should we think of a science which primly
abstracts from this large area of human labor, and fails to sense
its own inadequacy, even though such an extended wealth of
human activity says nothing more to it perhaps than what can
be said in one word—‘need’, ‘common need’?” (Karl Marx,
1975: p. 354) In Manifesto of the Communist Party (1848),
Marx and Engels blamed the founders of critical-utopian so-
cialism and communism who only knew to search “new social
laws”, but ignored historical conditions of the emancipation of
the proletariat. In Introduction to a Contribution to a Critique
of Political Economy (1857-1858), Marx stressed that when we
talked about the production, we referred to production at a cer-
tain stage of social development, there was no so-called abso-
lute law of “ production in general”. Even if we speak of “gen-
eral laws” on the common sense, this “general” concept itself
were multifarious compound comprising divergent categories.
Some elements were found in all epochs, some were common
to a few epochs. The purpose emphasized these “general laws”
only to avoid repetition, thus the most important thing for us to
do was not to highlight the common, but to emphasize the es-
sential differences. However, modern economists did not per-
ceive this fact, all wisdom of them were used to prove the eter-
nity of the laws of existing social relations. After the publica-
tion of Das Kapital, Marx’s scientific method was misunder-
stood and critiqued. In 1872, Marx endorsed the view attributed
to him in afterword to the second German edition of Das
Kapital that: “But it will be said, the general laws of economic
life are one and the same, no matter whether they are applied to
the present or the past. This Marx directly denies. According to
him, such abstract laws do not exist. On the contrary, in his
opinion every historical period has laws of its own…” (Karl
Marx, 1982: p. 18). In 1877, when someone wanted to change
Marx’s theory about the history of western European capitalist
development thoroughly into a general theory of historical phi-
losophy, Marx said: “He is both honoring and shaming me too
much… events strikingly analogous but taking place in differ-
ent historic surroundings led to totally different results. By
studying each of these forms of evolution separately and then
comparing them one can easily find the clue to this phenome-
non, but one will never arrive there by the universal passport of
a general historico-philosophical theory, the supreme virtue of
which consists in being super-historical.” (Marx/Engels, 1968:
p. 111). By the word of “super-historical”, Marx distinguished
his scientific theory from all categories of knowledge which
regarded seeking eternal laws and general truth as their essen-
tial mission (Chang, 2012).
Engels also has elaborated this view clearly. Soon after the
publication of Das Kapital, Engels pointed out that, whatever
the fate of the propositions of this book, a lasting merit of Marx
is to have put an end to the narrow-minded concept which
treated political economy “as abstract and universally valid a
science as mathematics”. Due to Marx’s historical outlook, it is
impossible to view social laws as “eternally valid truths”
(Marx/Engels, 1985: p. 218). In the difficult exploration about
the scientificity of Marxism theory, Louis Althusser also found
that when Marx said in a sarcastic tone that he was not a Marx-
ist, Marx actually opposed to describe his works as the general
philosophy of history or the political economy finding total law
of human society by a “writer”. And actually, Marx claimed
that Das Kapital was not a “science” (Althusser, 2003: p. 251).
Professor He Ping, a Chinese scholar, put forward this point in
Open Access 477