Theoretical Economics Letters, 2013, 3, 229-232
http://dx.doi.org/10.4236/tel.2013.34039 Published Online August 2013 (http://www.scirp.org/journal/tel)
Modelling Consumer Behavior by Inverse Demand
Functions
Susanne Fuchs-Seliger
Institut für Volkswirtschaftslehre Karlsruher Institut für Technologie, Karlsruher, Deutschland
Email: susanne.fuchs-seliger@kit.edu
Received June 4, 2013; revised July 4, 2013; accepted July 18, 2013
Copyright © 2013 Susanne Fuchs-Seliger. This is an open access article distributed under the Creative Commons Attribution License,
which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
ABSTRACT
In this article a model of consumer behavior will be developed, based on preferences on the price space reflecting the
individual’s willingness to pay for certain quantities of commodities under the supposition that the individual is re-
stricted to his or her income. Firms offer certain amounts of commodities at the market and consumers react to these
offers by their willingness to pay. Existence and continuity of the inverse demand function describing consumer’s be-
havior under appropriate conditions will be shown. Furthermore, differences between a model of consumer behavior
based on preferences on the commodity space and that which is based on preferences on the price space will be pointed
out.
Keywords: Consumer Theory; Preference Relation; Inverse Demand Functions; Duality Theory
1. Introduction
We will consider inverse demand functions which assign,
to every commodity bundle x, those market price com-
binations p the individual is willing to pay for x at most
when income M prevails. The demand function, defined
on prices and income, and the related inverse demand
function, defined on commodities offered at the market
and on the individual’s income, are dual concepts de-
scribing consumer behavior. According to its definition,
a demand function associates with every budget set

,BpMxXpx M 
Inverse demand functions often are a convenient tool
for modelling market behavior in the presence of mono-
polistic firms ([1], p. 326). If the firms have information
about the individual’s preferences on prices, then they
will know that he or she cannot accept prices higher than
a certain limit.
The analysis in this article will be based on preference
relations on prices instead of indirect utility functions.
Therefore, a more general framework for inverse demand
will be established. We will introduce axioms concerning
consumer’s preferences on the price space IRn
. Based
on these axioms properties of the inverse demand func-
tion will be deduced. For comparison, we will also point
out the difference between a model of consumer behavior
based on preferences on the commodity space and that
which is based on the price space.
, that commodity bundle
which according to the preferences of the individual is
the one he or she prefers to the other ones available in the
given budget set. From the point of duality, according to
the individual’s preferences with regard to prices, the
inverse demand function points out that price com-
bination the individual would spend for x at most, given
income
M
. As an example we may consider the fol-
lowing one: the individual is not willing to pay more than
two Euro for one pound of bred. Then he can afford to
buy cheese for not more than three Euro and ham for two
Euro. In total the individual cannot spend more than
seven Euro for these goods. Evidently, he would be
happy if these commodities were cheaper. As another
example we can fancy a market where carpets are sold
and the agent is not willing to pay more than a certain
amount of money for a special carpet.
2. Hypotheses on Consumer’s Preferences
Modelling consumer’s behavior we will assume the
following hypotheses:
(P1) is a relation on the strictly positive n-dimen-
sional vector space
IR n
. Every represents IRn
p
an income-normalized price vector, i.e. P
p
M
, where
IRn
P
are the market prices, i is the price of one
unit of the good
P
i
x
, and M is the income of the indi-
vidual, where .
0M
C
opyright © 2013 SciRes. TEL
S. FUCHS-SELIGER
230
(P2) is transitive and complete1.
(P3) is continuous, i.e.
(P3.1)
0
IR n
pp

p is closed in for every IRn

0IRn
p
(lower semicontinuity),
(P3.2)
0
IRn
ppp

2
is closed in for every IRn

0IRn
p
(upper semicontinuity).
(P4) , where is the asym-
metric part of 2.
12 1
pp pp
(P5) Let ,IR
kk n
pp 
, be a sequence such that
0
lim 0
k
kpp
 , where 0I, and R
n
IRn
p
k
. Then
there exists a positive integer such that for
all .
Npp
kN
The term means: the consumer either prefers
the price vector to or he is indifferent between
them. (P4) should be interpreted as follows: if the
individual can achieve a commodity bundle
pp
p p
x
in the
price situation at which all of the commodity prices
are lower than those in the price situation , then the
individual prefers to .
1
p
1
p
2
p
2
p
(P5) can be interpreted as: if the prices of some goods
turn to 0, then the value of the whole price systems
increases and becomes greater than any given positive
price system . However, the value may not converge
to infinity, but to a point of saturation. (P5) is a regularity
condition for proving Theorem 1 and 3. In reality no
market price turns to 0.
p
3. Inverse Demand Functions
Let us consider a commodity space and the
price space . Then the mapping
, is called an “inverse demand
correspondence’’. If is single-valued, then is
called an inverse demand function. denotes the
power set of .
IRn
X
IR
2n

IRn


,
nb

IR n

IR
:2bX x
bx
Bx

b
By we will denote all those income-normalized
price vectors at which
x
is available, i.e.

IR 1
n
Bx ppx

 . It has been shown (see [2],
Theorem 1, pp. 241-242), that the correspondence

IR
: IR2, IR1
n
n
BBxp


n
px

, is lower he-
micontinuous.
The inverse demand function corresponds to the in-
direct utility function being the dual counterpart to the
(direct) utility function to which the demand function
corresponds [3]. Given an indirect utility function v or,
more generally, a preference relation on the (in-
come-normalized) price space , we will ask when
the equality
IRn

 
IR: ,
n
ppBxpBxpp
 
  (1)
holds. Then we can define an inverse demand corre-
spondence IR
: 2n
bX
such that
 
IRnp B
: bxpxpBx pp

 
 . Thus,
bx points out special real price vectors IRn
P
at
income M of those price vectors, which are at the
individual’s disposal so that Px M, i.e. 1
P
px x
M
,
holds (for ) when commodity bundle x is
available at the market.
0M
By interpretation,
bx represents the set of all those
income-normalized price vectors which are most un-
favourable in the budget set according to the in-
dividual’s opinion. Therefore, producers of the com-
modity bundle

Bx
x
should know that the individual will
not accept prices still worse than those indicated by
bx. In case the profit maximizing firms are content
with those prices, a market equilibrium can be attained.
In view of (P4)
bx consists of the highest prices the
individual is willing to pay at most for
x
under the
restriction that he or she is limitated by his or her
income.
If
bx
IR
:
satisfies equality (1), then we will also call
2
n
bX
IR
X
as to be “consistent with ”. The above
definition of consistency can be considered as the dual
counterpart to rationality of demand correspondences
with respect to a given relation on the commodity
space
R
n
, i.e.:

: ,hpxXxB pyB pxRy

 
where
1, IR.
n
Bpz Xpzp
 
For comparison, if we start describing consumer be-
havior based on preferences on the commodity space,
then one can impose the following hypotheses (A1) to
(A4) on the commodity space
X
, and on the relation
on
R
X
:
(A1) , is supposed to be a closed set
of alternatives.
IR,
n
XX

(A2) is a reflexive relation on
R
X
.
(A3) is upper semicontinuous on
R
X
, i.e.
RxyyXyRx is closed in
X
for all
x
X
.
(A4) For all

zRy, zXPz y 
yX is
supposed to be convex and non-empty.
Then

: hpxxB pyB pxRy

 
(see [4], p. 303).
We can realize that these hypotheses are quite mild.
Even transitivity and completeness of the individual’s
preferences on the commodity space are not assumed.
The proof has been done by the help of the finite inter-
section property since the budget sets
1,IR:
n
p
pppp


 p
.
21
1, IR
n
Bpx Xpxp
 , are compact. How-
2
p
p means, 12
ii
p
pin.
Copyright © 2013 SciRes. TEL
S. FUCHS-SELIGER 231
ever, since

IR 1
n
Bx ppx

  is not compact,
the finite intersection property cannot be applied for
showing , and we therefore need different
assumptions.

bx
If we assume (P1) to (P5), then follows.
This will be shown by the next theorem.

bx
Theorem 1 Let the commodity space be the IRn
and assume (P1) to (P5). Then for all ,
IR n
x
 
IR :
n
bxpp BxpBxpp

  
.
Proof.
By assumption is a complete, transitive and con-
tinuous relation on . Therefore, by Debreu’s re-
presentation theorem [5], it can be represented by a
continuous function such that
 . The function
will be interpreted as an indirect utility function. In view
of (P4) is decreasing3. It suffices to show now, that
for all ,
v
vp

IRn

:IRn
, ,
IR
 
IR n
pp


p pvp

v
IR n
x
v

 

IR :
.
n
bx
ppBxpBxvpvp
 
 

Since is decreasing

vp




inf1, IR
inf1, IR
inf .
n
n
vp pxp
vp pxp
Mx




We will now continue strictly according to the proof of
Theorem 3 in [2], pp. 242-243. For abbreviation set

inf
s
Mx. One can show that in view of the
continuity of and of (P4) there exists

vp IRn
p
such that . Constructing a sequence

svp
1, 1
k
ss k
k
 , it follows that for every k
s
there
exists pk such that and 1
k
px

kk
s
vp s
. Since
k
p is bounded there exists a convergent subsequence
of k
p, denoted by
j
k
p such that 0
jpp

lim j
k
,
and

lim lim2
jj
kk
jj
p
svp ssv
 




. Hence, there
does not exist a positive integer such that
N2
j
kp
p
for all . Application of (P5) to this result implies
. In view of the continuity of we obtain
jN

j
k
00pv

0
lim
jvp vp
 , and therefore . Since

0
vp s

inf
s
Mx and since 01px
, we have
0, Ippp

Rn
 such that . Therefore 1px
 
0IR :
n
pppBxpBx vpvp
 
 .
Hence,
bx
IRn
and thus can be well defined for
all
b
x
.
This concludes our proof.
If the inverse demand function is based on an indirect
utility function satisfying the following condition ([2], p.
240):
(γ) for every sequence

0
, IR, 0
kk nkk
ppp pvp
 




, then
(P5) follows. Hence,
is stronger than (P5).
Lemma 2 Consider a continuous indirect utility func-
tion : vIR IR
n
satisfying condition
. Then
the corresponding preference relation defined by
:p pvpvp

, satisfies (P5).
Proof.
Given a sequence of price vectors k
p, IR
kn
p
,
such that , and a . By
0
lim 0
k
kpp
 IRn
p
it
follows
vp 
k. Since and since

IRvp
k
vp , there exsists a positive integer N such that
for all ,
kN
k
vp vp, and hence , con-
cluding our proof.
k
pp
According to (P5) the indirect utility function may
converge to a finite value when . There-
fore, condition (P5) is weaker than
v
00
k
pp

.
4. Some Properties of the Inverse Demand
Correspondence
It will now be shown that is upper
hemicontinuous. We will characterize upper hemicon-
tinuity by sequences ([6], pp. 262-263, Theorem A III. 1,
part (b) of the proof, where compact-valuedness of the
correspondence is not needed, see also [7], p. 532,
Theorem 16.17):
:IR2 n
R
n
b

Let , where , then
:2
T
FS,IR
n
ST
F
is called
“upper hemicontinuous” at 0
x
S, if for every sequence
k
x
with 0
lim
k
k
x
x

and for every sequence k
y
with
k
yFxk
, there exists a convergent subsequence
of ,
kkj
yy, such that lim
j s called
upper hemicontinuous if it is upper hemicontinuous at

0kj
yyFx . F i
every
x
S
.
Theorem 3 If the relation satisfies (P1) to (P5)
an
d if :IR2 n
R
n
b
 is consistent with , then b is
upper h
Proof.
emicontinuous.
Let ,IR
kkn
xx
, be a sequence such that
lim IR
kx
kn
x
 
n
s, for any k and for all . Thu
IRp
such that 1
k
px
it flows, k
pp
3The (income normalized) indirect utility function v is called decreasing
ol , where
if
 
p
pvpvp

 , for all . , IRn
pp 
Copyright © 2013 SciRes. TEL
S. FUCHS-SELIGER
Copyright © 2013 SciRes. TEL
232
k
pbx
k
and k
pp p. If

1,,
kk
n
k
p is not
bounded, thust exist a postegeen there mitive inr jn
and a sequence k
j
p such that lim k
j
p
 . Since
j
, we obtain for some
lim 0
jj
kxx
 
kkk 1
ll
px INm
and for all ing
lm, contradict1
k
. Hence
k
px k
p
nece
e O
is bounded, herefore, takinguence if -
ssary, lim k
pp
 . In order to obtain a contradiction,
and t a subseq
k
suppos bviously, there exists
0p
.IRn
p
such
that 1
. Spxince lim k
k
x
x
 there also exists an inte-
ger such that
10N for all 1: 1
k
kNpx. Hence,
by ccy, onsistenk
pp. On th5) yields
the existence of an integer 20N such that for all
2
kN,
e other side, (P
k
pp. Take
12
ma ,NNN
, then for all
x
kN
, k
pp and k
pction. Hence, p, a co

pbx
n that
ntradi
showTherefore, let us
co
e exists a positive integer such that
2)
0.
Now, it will be
p

.
ˆ1px
. I
wo
nsider ˆIRn
p
such that n order to obtain
that p
ve to consider tcases.
1) .
ˆ
p
, we ha
1
ˆ
px
Hen erce, thN
,
ˆ
px
kN.
k
1
k for all kN, and therefore ˆ
k
pp, for all
In view ofr semicontinuity o
ˆ
pp.
lowef
lim
kp

ˆ1px
.
Let, IR
ll n
qq 
, be a sequence such that
and qu
does exist.e hav
we thus ob
Corollary: In t
re
ˆ
lim
kp

l
q1. Obviously, such a se
l
qx
ence
Since we 1
lk
qx for some positive in-
teger ˆ
N and for all k obtain kl
pq. By
lower micontinuity thplies, lim kl
p. In
ˆ
N
, we
s im
sei kq
 p
view of upper semicontinuity of tain ,
ud
ˆ
pp
. Hence

pbx

. This concles our proof
of Lemma 2 and the previous he light
marks it follows: given a continuous and decreasing
indirect utility function v: IRIR
n

satisfying con-
dition

, then the inverseespondence b:
IR n
n
 , defined by

demand corr
IR
2
 
Bx vp
 
,for alvp


lpB x

upper hemicontinuous.
concavity of implies single-
va or
bx p is
Finally, since strict
luedness of the inverse demand crespondence we
immediately obtain the following theorem. Preliminarily,
remember that strict concavity is defined as follows: let
Y be a convex set, and let ,ppY
with pp
,
n: the

0pp p p
 
,1
.
d let it be
1,p


P1) to (P5)Theorem 4 Let satisfy ( an
n
strictly concave, the
a)
bx is single-valued if nsistent b is cowith ,
and bIR
nn
: IR

is a continuous function,
b) etic4, then b is homogene if is homothous of
degree 1
.
Note,at th upper hemicontinuitynt
5. Summary
analysis, a fo for m
REFERE
A. Mas-Colell, R. Green
y of Value:atic An
liger, “A Note on Cons
and co
rmal frame
NCES
An Axiom
Duality in
inuity are
odelling
, “Micro-
alysis of
umer The-
ide
[1]
ntical, when b is a function ([6], p. 262).
In the previous
consumer behavior has been presented when firms offer
certain amounts of commodities at the market and con-
sumers react to these offers by their willingness to pay.
This willingness to pay can be described by the inverse
demand correspondence. When the plans of consumers
and firms coincide then the deal will take place, and the
consumers will achieve the goods.
M. D. Whinston and J.
economic Theory, Volume 1,” Oxford University Press,
New York, 1995.
[2] G. Debreu, “Theor
Economic Equilibrium,” Yale University Press, New Ha-
ven, 1959.
[3] S. Fuchs-Se
ory,” Economic Theory, Vol. 13, No. 1, 1999, pp. 239-
246. doi:10.1007/s001990050252
[4] W. Erwin Diewert, “Applications of Duality The
sated and Direct
ory,” In:
Demand
M. D. Intriligator and D. A. Kendrick, Eds., Frontiers of
Quantitative Economics, Vol. II, North-Holland, Am-
sterdam, 1974, pp. 106-176.
[5] S. Fuchs-Seliger, “Compen
without Transitive and Complete Preferences,” Annals of
Operations Research, Vol. 23, No. 1, 1990, pp. 299-310.
doi:10.1007/BF02204854
[6] C. D. Aliprantis and C. Kim, “Infinite Dime
denbrand and A. P Kirman, “Equilibriu
0
nsional Ana-
m Analy-
lysis: Hitchhikers Guide,” Springer-Verlag, New York,
1986.
[7] W. Hil
sis,” North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam,
1988.
4 is called “homothetic”, if ,>xyxy

 .