Open Journal of Philosophy
2012. Vol.2, No.3, 195-201
Published Online August 2012 in SciRes (http://www.SciRP.org/journal/ojpp) http://dx.doi.org/10.4236/ojpp.2012.23030
Copyright © 2012 SciRes. 195
Dutch-Book Arguments against Using Conditional Probabilities
for Conditional Bets
Keith Hutchison
School of Historical and Philosophical Studies, University of Melbourne, Parkville, Australia
Email: keithrh@gmail.com
Received April 22nd, 2012; revised May 24th, 2012; accepted June 10th, 2012
We consider here an important family of conditional bets, those that proceed to settlement if and only if
some agreed evidence is received that a condition has been met. Despite an opinion widespread in the lit-
erature, we observe that when the evidence is strong enough to generate certainty as to whether the condi-
tion has been met or not, using traditional conditional probabilities for such bets will not preserve a gam-
bler from having a synchronic Dutch Book imposed upon him. On the contrary (I show) the gambler can
be Dutch-Booked if his betting ratios ever depart from a rather different probability, one that involves the
probability of the agreed evidence being provided. We note furthermore that this same alternative prob-
ability assessment is necessary if the evidence is weaker (i.e. if it fails to provide knowledge whether or
not the condition has been met). By contrast, some of the (rather different) probability assessments pro-
posed by Jeffrey, precisely for such situations, still expose the gambler to a Dutch-Book.
Keywords: Probability; Conditioning; Dutch-Book; Conditional Probability; Bayesianism;
Jeffrey Conditioning
Introduction
My core task below is to refute a common belief about con-
ditional probabilities, the claim that such probability assess-
ments preserve a gambler from having a Dutch-Book imposed
upon him when he makes an important type of conditional bet,
one that proceeds to settlement if and only if the participating
gamblers find out that some agreed condition has been met. The
discussion below, accordingly, is set in the standard Dutch-
Book context: i.e. two gamblers (Peter and Mary say) are bet-
ting against each other on the outcomes of some chance-process,
with Peter setting the odds through his assessments of the
probability p(Z) of each outcome Z, and Mary setting the bets.
It is well-known that if Peter’s odds are “coherent” (i.e. obey
the basic laws of probability), Mary cannot offer Peter a book
composed of simple bets that will result in a net gain for Mary
no matter which of the possible outcomes Z eventuates. For the
purposes of the discussion here, we shall call such a book
“Dutch” (and we will refer to the gains that it provides Mary as
“sure”, or “guaranteed” etc.)1.
The existence of such a Dutch-Book is often taken as evi-
dence that Peter’s odds are irrational, but that judgment is a
little hasty. For in many circumstances, Peter can find himself
guaranteeing Mary a profit, because of simple ignorance, as
opposed to some blemish of reasoning—as becomes fleetingly
important at the very end of our discussion. Though quite fa-
miliar, this possibility is often blurred in the literature, so we
need to distinguish two types of Dutch-Books: “weak” ones,
those that result from ignorance, and which cannot accordingly
be anticipated by Peter; and “stronger” ones—where Peter pos-
sesses enough information to perceive his odds will allow a
guaranteed loss to be imposed upon him. Not all stronger
Dutch-Books are, however, evidence of irrationality either, but
we can avoid confronting this issue. Except for the cases briefly
mentioned in my search for a converse below, all the Dutch-
Books used in the argumentation below will be of the “irra-
tional” type.
It is widely recognized that Peter’s safety-net can be ex-
tended beyond simple bets, to an important category of condi-
tional bets. If a bet on X is to proceed to settlement when and
only when the outcome Y has been achieved, Peter is protected
if he accepts bets based on the “conditional probability”
p(X&Y)/p(Y), abbreviated here as p(X/Y)2. Let us call such bets
“ontic” conditional bets, because they proceed if and only if the
outcome at issue has come into existence. We need to give
them a name, for our aim here is to point out that the familiar
safety-net does not extend to a wider class of conditional bets.
If indeed we attend to the distinction between a proposition’s
2A number of theorists do not treat p(X/Y) as an abbreviation, but as a
primitive notion, “the probability of X given Y”. For our present pur
p
oses,
this approach is too ambiguous however, for “given Y” can mean either
“given the truth of Y” or “given a knowledge of Y”. An ongoing theme o
f
this paper could then be rephrased as the pair of claims: a) that these two
quantities are different, and b) that p(X/Y) in the first sense is not suitable
for epistemic conditional bets. The relationship between such conditional
bets and the second, epistemic, sense of p(X/Y) is more complicated: for
“diachronic” books (those involving probabilities that change in the course
of time), become involved. The analysis thus expands to hazier “kinematic”
issues outside the deliberately focussed scope of this essay—the synchronic
context set by the literature I seek to refute. Indeed, a common way o
f
interpreting conditional probabilities is to presume (in the example used
b
elow) they refer to new assessments of probability that Peter adopts
around the time τ + 4 (in time-line below). In virtually all the discussion
here, probability assessments are made at the one time (τ – 2), and the same
applies to stakes (τ – 1).
1We will not (as sometimes suggested) require a Dutch-Book to guarantee a
p
rofit whatever happens, for that is exceptionally vague, and far too broad.
So if gamblers are betting on the toss of a normal coin, identification of a
Dutch-Book will not require us to show that a profit would occur even if the
head on the coin mysteriously turned into a tail during the toss, or worse, i
f
the world was destroyed before the coin landed.
K. HUTCHISON
being ascertained and its being true3, we will observe that such
ontic bets are distinct from “epistemic” ones—which proceed if
and only if the outcome Y has been detected. Epistemic condi-
tional bets are far more realistic than the ontic ones, for ordi-
nary gamblers cannot be expected to settle a bet if its precondi-
tion is not known to be true—even if it is in fact true. They are,
too, the sort of bets that specially interest Bayesians, for the
core of Bayesianism is analysis of the effects of new informa-
tion. In many artificial situations of course (especially those
typical of the text-book, casino, or appeals to god), the truth or
falsity of the applicable condition is always ascertained, so the
distinction between the two classes of bet fades. But this is not
generally true.
There is a presumption throughout the literature that the ar-
gument which preserves a gambler from being Dutch-Booked
via ontic conditional bets, covers the epistemic ones as well4. But
that is definitely not true. Demonstrating this fact is the central
task undertaken in the present essay—which thus supplements an
earlier piece of mine (Hutchison, 1999), that demonstrated the
inadequacy of conditional probability as a procedure for updat-
ing probabilities in the light of supplementary evidence.
The core of the present argument is the simple counter-ex-
ample set out with pedantic care below. It quickly shows that
various Dutch-Books (of the irrational kind) can be set up
against Peter, if Peter adopts the strategy of betting on an out-
come X at the rate p(X&Y)/p(Y) when bets are settled if and
only if the outcome Y is detected. Peter, indeed, will not be able
to rely on a calculation that (like the traditional formula) uses
only the probabilities he attributes to the outcomes of the
chance-process under observation. For protection against Dutch-
Books, he needs to supplement these probabilities with some-
thing else: those associated with the gamblers’ finding out that
the outcome was Y.
To establish the alternative calculation that Peter needs to use,
our discussion (following the initial presentation of the main
counter-example) becomes distinctly more complicated, but
only superficially so, in that we have to juggle a multiplicity of
probabilities. We then extend this key result even further, show-
ing that our alternative formula applies when bets are made con-
ditional upon the receipt of evidence for Y, and that evidence falls
short of providing knowledge that the outcome Y has been
achieved. This situation is sometimes supposed to be covered
by Jeffrey’s extended rule of conditioning (see n. 9), but we
show that this rule advises Peter to use rather different betting
ratios, and that these do not suffice to exclude a Dutch-Book.
As befits the fact that I am arguing against a received claim,
my focus will be almost exclusively on the “synchronic” books
used in the literature that I target, those in which all bets are
placed at the one time. Diachronic books (i.e. those composed
of bets placed at different times) generate dramatic complica-
tions for the Dutch-Book approach—see e.g. n. 5—and accord-
ingly are given only passing mention below, though I have
discussed the inadequacy of conditional probability in their
context elsewhere (see Hutchison, 1999).
The Betting Scenario for the Main Example
To make the case, we consider a very simple urn model.
(Many readers will recognize this to be an adaption of Ber-
trand’s box paradox, but that fact is not important to following
the analysis below). We will be supposing that (at some time
we shall call τ) an honest (etc.) coordinator Paul places three
unbiased coins in an urn: one normal coin (with a head and a
tail face); one with two head faces; and one with two tail faces.
Later, at time τ + 1, Paul randomly selects one of these coins
from the urn, and Peter and Mary bet against each other on
(inter alia) the various outcomes of this draw. These bets can be
simple; or conditional upon information released by Paul.
3As evidenced by the citations in n. 4 below, there is remarkable little atten-
tion to this distinction in the probability literature. It is, fleetingly, recog-
nised as being a problem in the subjective interpretation, but seemingly
tolerated. Hacking, 1967: pp. 316, 324 treats it as a “trifling idealization”
typical of those made in philosophical analysis; while Weatherson, 2003
and Harman, 1983 note that the blurring creates an affinity with intuitionist
logic, without however observing the dramatically disruptive consequences
within more standard logics. Howson & Urbach, 2006: p. 54 avoid the issue
b
y presuming (in one particularly sensitive context) that bets are settled by
an “omniscient oracle”.
4Because the literature on probability is reluctant to distinguish the two
types of bets (and more generally, to accommodate the distinction
between truth and ascertainment), we know of no overt declaration that
the one argument covers both cases. But it is routine to find an
equivocation in the interpretation of the result at issue in the context o
f
discussions of the Dutch-Book defence of conditionalization. See, e.g.:
De Finetti, 1974-1975, v.1: p. 135 (“if H does not turn out to be true”;
“if I know H is true”; brief cryptic reference to Dutch-Book); Gillies,
2000: pp. 36-37 (where conditional probabilities are introduced as i
f
they refer to what is ascertained) and p. 62 (where the Ramsey-De
Finetti theorem is stated in terms of truth—with bets being called off i
f
a condition “does not occur”—then defended via a Dutch-Book argu-
ment); Talbott, 2008: p. 2 (where conditionalization is characterised
epistemically) and p. 3 (where the Dutch-Book argument is phrased in
terms of a bet called off if a condition is not true); Howson, 1977: p. 63
(middle paragraph, where the conclusion of the Dutch-Book argument
is summed up in terms of both truth and verification); Teller, 1973: p.
220 (where the problem is phrased in terms of ascertainment), p. 222
(where the reference class singled out by ascertainment is identified
with that provided by truth), p. 224 (where the circumstances in which
bets are called off is characterised via truth); Skyrms, 1987: p. 2
(where the problem is phrased in terms of ascertainment), p. 3 (where
the circumstances in which bets are called off is characterised via
truth
.
For after he makes the draw, Paul is to release information to
Paul and Mary, via a two-stage process (summarized in the
time-line depicted below). The second stage is rather trite and
takes place at time τ + 5, when Paul reveals full details of the
selected coin, so that bets can be settled (at τ + 6). The first stage
is far more significant here, for this takes place earlier (at time τ +
3), when Paul provides the partial information about the draw
that allows epistemic conditional betting. Paul inspects the coin
that has been drawn, and reveals something about it via proce-
dures specified in the individual examples below.
We suppose that Peter and Mary have both understood all
Paul’s proposed actions since well before they were actually
carried out, and that each of them also understands that the other
possesses the same comprehension of the processes. So all that
they later discover is the results of those activities. To avoid all
irrelevant confusion about the temporal sequence of events, we
suppose that this understanding of the process was in place at
time τ – 3, and we shall be irritatingly careful to stress the tim-
ings of all later activity (as summarized in our time-line, Figure
1). In the end, these timings are not very important, but it is vital
that there be no room for confusion about them.
It may not be important here that Mary know that Peter shares
her understanding of the betting process, but Peter’s realization
that Mary understands what is going on does seem vital to the
logic—because this, in the end, is what makes the Dutch-Books
below evidence of Peter’s irrationality in agreeing to bet on stan-
dard conditional probabilities. For it means that Peter has enough
Copyright © 2012 SciRes.
196
K. HUTCHISON
Figure 1.
TIME-LINE (left): the precise sequence of events in our counter-ex-
amples: placing bets; drawing coin; releasing information; settling bets.
The two separate chance-processes involved (right).
information to realize that Mary has access to the various prof-
itable algorithms articulated below5. Reason alone can then tell
Peter that in allowing Mary to set the bets, he has in effect
agreed to give Mary full access to his bank account. She can
take from him as much money as she wants, and (granted she is
able to do the requisite arithmetic etc.) is restrained by nothing
more than her willingness to act.
After he has acquired this understanding of what was going
to happen, but still before the chance-process actually begins,
Peter announces (at time τ – 2 say) the probabilities that he was
willing to bet on here; and bets are subsequently offered by
Mary (at time τ – 1).
Amongst the probabilities announced by Peter at time τ – 2,
are his degrees-of-belief in the various outcomes Z of the draw
that Paul is soon to make. These generate a very simple prob-
ability function p(Z), which (in addition to 0 and 1) takes the
following values:
13 = p(HH) for the selected coin having two
heads (which we call outcome “HH”);
13
= p(TT) for the selected coin having two tails
(outcome “TT”);
13 = p(HT) for the selected coin having exactly
one head and one tail (outcome “HT”);
23 = p(H) for the selected coin having at least
one head (outcome “H”);
23 = p(T) for the selected coin having at least
one tail (outcome “T”).
Principal Counter-Example
To generate our first pool of conditional bets, we suppose
that Paul is to release his partial information, by uttering (at
time τ + 3) precisely one word, either “Head” or “Tail”. Paul
chooses between these two utterances by tossing (at time τ + 2)
the coin previously selected (at time τ + 1). If this coin comes
up heads at time τ + 2, Paul says “Head” at time τ + 3, but if it
comes up tails he says “Tail”. Since Peter has understood (since
time τ – 3) that this is how Paul was going to behave, Peter
allocates (at time τ – 2) the probability 12 to each utterance.
So (at time τ – 2) Peter declares himself ready to bet (at time τ
1) on either utterance at this rate.
It is important to note that Paul’s utterance emerges from a
subsidiary—observational—chance-process that occurs between
times τ + 2 and τ + 3, distinctly after the primary chance-proc-
ess that is the nominal focus of the betting, the one that occurs
between times τ and τ + 1. As reflects the fact that the informa-
tion comes from a very different chance-process, the probabil-
ity (12) that Peter allocates to finding out the selected coin has
at least one tail is less than the probability (23
) he allocates to
its being true that it has at least one tail. Peter is clearly right
here6, and furthermore, this divergence between the two prob-
abilities is at the heart of the matter at hand: bets that refer to
what is known (as opposed to what is true) need to allow for the
supplementary probabilities allocated to the outcomes of the
observational chance-process.
To see this, we now enquire what fair betting-ratios Peter
should endorse for bets on HH, HT, and TT, if such bets are
conditional, and only proceed (beyond time τ + 4) when Peter
and Mary have found out (at time τ + 3) that the draw produced
at least one tail?7 Obviously, they acquire this knowledge if and
only if Paul says “Tail” (at time τ + 3) (If this happens, bets on
HH will not, of course, proceed).
If Peter recognizes the affinity between our betting scenario
and the literature on Bertrand’s box paradox, he could well be
guided by that literature to assess the probabilities to be used
for his conditional bets on HT and TT as 13
and 32
. But he
could instead be guided by rather different literature, an unsat-
isfactory literature which clashes with the box literature, and
the literature which is our prime target here. That is the impor-
6Since this divergence plays a critical role below, it might seem that a radi-
cally subjectivist Peter can avoid our Dutch-Book by insisting that his
degree-of-belief in the “Tail”-utterance is actually somewhat higher. But
then he exposes himself to other Dutch-Books. For if his degree-of-belief in
the “Head”-utterance does not drop, he can be Dutch-Booked on the
“Head” and “Tail” probabilities alone. And when it does drop, he falls prey
to a Dutch-Book identical to that set out below, but with Heads and Tails
interchanged.
7More carefully: What fair betting-ratios should Peter endorse (back at time
τ – 2) for bets with Mary (at time τ – 1) on the three possible outcomes o
f
the original draw (viz.: HH, HT, TT)—the outcomes that get revealed in a
full inspection (at time τ + 5) of the selected coin—if such bets are now
conditional, and only proceed (beyond τ + 4) when Peter and Mary find out
(at time τ + 3) that the draw at time τ + 1 produced at least one tail?
5Irrationality definitely requires more than a) Peter having enough under-
standing to be able to see that a Dutch-Book exists, or b) that Mary be able
to see the same thing. For if we briefly consider bets placed at different
times, it is easy to show that a diachronic Dutch-Book exists whenever
Peter changes his betting ratios. Yet rationality often requires him to do this
(typically, when new evidence arises). Mary can then stumble upon a
Dutch-Book, but she has no algorithm to construct it. For she cannot know
the appropriate initial bet until she also knows what change Peter is going to
make to his betting ratio.
Copyright © 2012 SciRes. 197
K. HUTCHISON
tant body of writings (as sampled in n. 4) which assures him
that using conditional probabilities is appropriate here. He
would then accept p(X&T)/p(T) [p(X/T)] as a fair basis for a
bet on any outcome X that is conditional upon the ascertainment
of the outcome T. Such probabilities are easy to evaluate and in
particular p(TT/T) is just p(TT&T)/p(T) = p(TT)/p(T) = 13
32
= 12.
These probabilities do not however protect Peter from being
Dutch-Booked. For suppose that Mary sets up the following
book:
Bet 1: Peter bets $4 in favour of the outcome TT.
i.e. he pays Mary $4, and in return:
Mary pays him $12 if (at time τ + 6), the TT coin is
found to have been drawn, for Peter’s fair betting
ratio here is p(TT) = 13.
She pays him nothing otherwise.
Bet 2: Mary bets $6 in favour of the draw producing exactly
two tails, but conditionally on at least one tail (outcome T)
being revealed (i.e. conditionally on Paul uttering “Tail” at
time τ + 3).
i.e. she pays Peter $6, and in return:
Peter pays her $12 (at time τ + 6) if two tails are
found (at time τ + 5) (for if the coin has two tails
Paul must utter “Tail” so the bet would not have
been cancelled, and Peter’s fair betting ratio here is,
by hypothesis, 12).
Peter pays her nothing if Paul utters “Tail” but a
head and tail are found at time τ + 5.
Peter refunds her $6 if Paul does not utter “Tail”.
Bet 3: Mary bets $3 in favour of the “Tail” utterance.
i.e. she pays Peter $3, and in return:
Peter pays her $6 (at time τ + 6) if Paul (at time τ +
3) utters “Tail” (for Peter’s fair betting ratio here is
12).
Peter pays her nothing if Paul utters “Head”.
In so far as he has set the odds for these three bets, Peter
claims to regard each of them as individually fair. Yet if he
accepts the whole book, Mary will make a profit of $1, no mat-
ter what outcome was produced in the original draw, or what
utterance Paul makes at τ + 3. This is clear in the tabulation of
her earnings set out in Table 1.
A little reflection will quickly indicate what has gone “wrong”
here: Paul’s “Tail”-message does not indicate that the initial draw
has produced a coin with a tail every time that it does produce
such a coin. There is indeed a 50% chance that the coin with one
head and one tail will produce the “Head”-message.
Given the circumstances which produce the “Tail”-message, Pe-
ter should actually adopt a probability of 23 (rather than 12)
Table 1.
Calculation of Mary’s winnings: Principal counter-example.
Bet 1: TT
(13)
Bet 2: TT/“Tail”
(12)
Bet 3: “Tail”
(12)
Outcome Loss Gain Loss Gain Loss Gain Net Gain
HH $0 $4 $6 $6 $3 $0 $1
TT $12 $4 $6 $12 $3 $6 $1
HT&“Tail” $0 $4 $6 $0 $3 $6 $1
HT&“Head” $0 $4 $6 $6 $3 $0 $1
for the conditional bet on TT—the probability suggested by the
box paradox literature. This 23 is still a conditional prob-
ability, but it is very different from that recommended in the
Dutch-Book literature, which endorses betting ratios derived
exclusively from the probabilities p(Z) of outcomes Z of the pri
mary chance-process. The safe probability, 23, is rather
π(TT/“Tail” uttered)—where π is the extension of p that covers
the composite chance process that stretches from time τ to τ + 3,
the primary process plus its epistemic coda8. If Peter used this
improved valuation, he would pay Mary only $9 if two tails
were confirmed, so she would then makes a net loss of $2 if the
coin had two tails. i.e. Peter would no longer be Dutch-Booked.
It might seem that this situation can be rectified by disallow-
ing the epistemic protocol specified in this counter-example,
the procedure followed by Paul in deciding whether to utter
“Head” or “Tail”. But that is thoroughly unsatisfactory—for
two quite different reasons. Firstly, it amounts to an admission
that conditional probabilities cannot handle thoroughly reason-
able epistemic behavior: it in effect concedes the very point that
we are trying to establish. Secondly, it does not solve the prob-
lem.
Subsidiary Counter-Example
For suppose we insist that Paul investigate the outcome of
the initial draw differently, indeed so thoroughly as to utter
“Tail” if and only if at least one side of the selected coin pos-
sessed a tail, and now ask that Peter again bet on the condi-
tional probabilities. Peter will not then be Dutch-Booked if he
buys the book we proposed for Mary in the principal counter-
example above. For Peter will now estimate the probability of
Paul uttering “Tail” to have increased to 23
, so some of
Mary’s income will be reduced. The $6 she wins on bet 3 when
Paul says “Tail”, will drop to $4.50, and the $1.50 reduction
here will wipe out her profit, and give her a 50c loss instead.
But Mary will now be able to offer a different book, that
shown by Table 2 to be Dutch, and consisting of just two bets,
one simple and the other conditional:
Bet 1: Mary bets $2 in favor of the coin having at least one tail.
i.e. she pays Peter $2, and in return:
Peter pays her $3 whenever the coin is TT or HT,
(for Peter assesses the probability of T as23).
Peter pays her nothing if the coin is HH.
Bet 2: Mary bets $3 on both sides of the coin being a head,
but conditionally on at least one head (outcome H) being
revealed, (i.e. conditionally on Paul uttering “Head” at time τ
+ 3).
i.e. she pays Peter $3, and in return:
Peter pays her $6 if Paul utters “Head”, (for by hy-
pothesis, Peter is ready to bet on the conditional
probability p(HH/H) (=12) here, and by hypothe-
sis also, Paul only utters “Head” when there is no
tail).
Peter refunds the $3 if Paul utters “Tail”.
8This follows simply from the standard result (which we do not challenge)
that conditional probabilities are necessary to avoid a Dutch- Book (of the
irrational kind) when bets proceed if and only if the specified condition is
true. This result is applied to the extended chance-
p
rocess that takes place
between times τ and τ + 3. Peter and Mary ascertain that the draw compo-
nent of this composite process produced at least one tail if and only if it is
true that the whole process produced the “Tail”-utterance outcome.
Copyright © 2012 SciRes.
198
K. HUTCHISON
Table 2.
Mary’s Winnings: subsidiary counter-example.
Bet 1: T (23) Bet 2: HH/“Head” (12)
Outcome Loss Gain Loss Gain Net Gain
HH $2 $0 $3 $6 $1
TT $2 $3 $3 $3 $1
HT $2 $3 $3 $3 $1
Generalizing the Counter-Example
In the discussion above, we presumed that Peter (and Mary)
knew how Paul was going to decide how to make his (τ +
3)-utterance, but such an assumption was not critical to our
revelation of the Dutch-Book. I now outline (in very brief sum-
mary) an argument that shows this, before we move on to a far
more general situation.
Imagine indeed that information about the initial draw is re-
leased by some procedure quite different to that used by Paul
above. But let us, for the moment, agree that Paul still informs
Peter and Mary of his procedure in advance of the placement of
bets; and for simplicity, let us require also that this procedure
includes a guarantee to utter exactly one of “Head” or “Tail”. If
Peter still uses standard conditional probabilities for epistemic
conditional bets, Mary can always construct a Dutch-Book
exploiting Peter’s choice of betting ratios.
It is well-known that Peter can be quickly Dutch-booked
(without recourse to conditional bets) if the probabilities he
allocates to the two utterances do not total to 1, so at least one
of the utterances can be presumed to have been allocated a
probability less than 23, say 1/α with α > 32 (This appar-
ently odd choice of α simplifies the arithmetic below). Suppose
(for the moment) that this applies to the “Tail”-utterance. All
Mary has to do to get her Dutch-Book is alter the stakes in the
bets comprising the principal counter-example above. A quick
(but slightly untidy) calculation shows that if she makes the
stake on the first bet
2α2α3
, that on the second bet
3α2α3, and that on the third bet 1 less than that on the
first bet, her winnings will always be 1. i.e. the book will be
Dutch. An analogous argument applies when only the “Head”-
utterance has a probability less than 23.
But suppose now that Peter is not told how Paul is to choose
whether to utter “Head” or “Tail”. Our gambler is faced with a
situation that commonly occurs in everyday life, where infor-
mation reaches us without our fully understanding how it came.
If Peter is still willing to set betting ratios for Paul’s utterances,
exactly the same Dutch-Book strategy continues to remain avail-
able to Mary, of course. For the “objective accuracy” (etc.) of
Peter’s π(“Tail”) did not play any role in generating our books.
As observed above, avoidance of a Dutch-Book requires that
Peter use (for bet 2) the rather different conditional probability,
Π(X&Y*)/Π(Y*), where Y* means “Y has been ascertained”, and
Π(W) is the probability Peter allocates to each outcome W of
that more extensive chance-process which supplements the
original chance activity with the subsequent observational
process (We use capital “P” and “Π” here, to distinguish gen-
eral probabilities from our concrete example, where we used
lower case “p” and “π”).
An Extension to Jeffrey Conditioning:
“Evidential” Conditional Bets
Imagine now that the lighting is to be dimmed between times
τ + 2 and τ + 3, so that Paul will not then get a really good look
at the coin, and is, he warns, likely to make an error in his iden-
tification of the face that is showing. Suppose however Paul
agrees to utter “Tail” when what he sees seems more like a tail
than a head. Then if Peter hears Paul utter “Tail” he is not going
to acquire knowledge that the outcome T has been achieved
(and vice versa for “Head” and H). Under such circumstances,
there is no temptation to use standard conditional probabilities
for conditional bets, since the circumstances that are alleged to
allow their use do not obtain.
Jeffrey however, has proposed an alternative probability that
might seem to be applicable here. For he suggests that if the
“Tail” utterance leaves Peter λ% certain that Paul has seen a tail,
and μ% certain that Paul has seen a head (where λ + μ = 100),
then, at time τ + 4, Peter should update his confidence that the
coin has two tails (say) from the prior value p(TT) = 33.333...%
to the posterior percentage λp(TT/T) + μp(TT/H)9. Though Jef-
frey articulates his revised rule in contexts that focus primarily
on diachronic processes (where gamblers place different bets at
different times), the rule makes sense in our more modest con-
text. So we can ask an obvious question: is it wise for Peter to
use Jeffrey-conditionalization for his conditional bets in the cir-
cumstances sketched above, where the information released by
Paul at time τ + 3 no longer provides knowledge that an outcome
has been achieved? Such conditional bets are no longer “epistemic”
then—in the sense contrasted with ontic bets above—and we will
here call them “evidential” since they continue if and only if an
agreed piece of evidence is obtained. If he wishes to avoid a
Dutch-Book, is it sufficient for Peter to use Jeffrey-conditionaliza-
tion when placing an evidentially conditional bet?
The answer to this question should be immediately clear: it is
definitely “NO”! For if the Jeffrey-conditionalization was truly
reliable here, it would have to work in the extreme cases, when
one of μ or λ was zero. But we have already seen that this is not
so. For in such circumstances, Jeffrey’s extended conditional
probability (at least that version of it articulated above) simply
collapses to the standard conditional probability. And by now,
we have repeatedly seen that the latter is enough to allow Mary
to construct Dutch-Books against Peter.
Furthermore, this form of Jeffrey’s extended rule becomes
totally redundant—for, as I will soon show, the conditional
probability Π(X&Y*)/Π(Y*) can in fact accommodate the situa-
tions envisaged by Jeffrey, while the Jeffrey rule allows a
Dutch-Book even when both μ and λ are non-zero. Indeed,
while it is true that the focus of this essay has until now been
articulated in terms of conditions that involved Peter being
supplied with knowledge (with some outcome of the primary
chance-process being reliably verified), that has in fact been
something of a red herring. It was there primarily because it
was required to make sense of the negative claim—the claim
about standard conditional probabilities that we have rejected
here. But if we focus on the alternative positive result—the
claim that Π(X&Y*)/Π(Y*) is required to avoid a Dutch-Book—
then a little reflection will indicate that there is no necessity at
all for Y* to be restricted to the narrow meanings given it above.
It can readily embrace evidential betting as well.
Indeed, we can easily generate an extremely general condi-
9See, e.g., Jeffrey, 1983: pp. 165-166.
Copyright © 2012 SciRes. 199
K. HUTCHISON
tional betting situation by imagining two different chance proc-
esses: process 1 that produces outcomes referred to here using
early letters of the alphabet, A, B, C,... etc.; and process 2 that
produces outcomes referred to here using late letters, Z, Y, X,...
etc. Peter does not presume these processes to be statistically
independent, so allocates joint probabilities Π(A&Z) to the
outcomes A and Z..., etc.; and we use Π(A) as an abbreviation
for Π(A&2) where 2 is the universal outcome for process 2;
Π(Z) is similarly defined in the obvious analogous fashion.
We can now ask the question what probabilities should be
used for bets on the outcomes of process 1, if those bets are
conditional, and proceed if and only if process 2 produces some
outcome Y? Suppose that Peter is willing to accept the betting
ratio 1/α for a conditional bet on B that proceeds if and only if Y
is produced. We show that if α is not Π(Y)/Π(B&Y), then again
a Dutch-Book can be constructed.
We ignore the cases when Peter makes either Π(B&Y) or Π(Y)
zero, for the relevant bets will not be placed if Peter does not
believe the condition will be met, or believes that B is incom-
patible with the condition. So we can make β 1/Π(B&Y) and
γ≡ 1/Π(Y), and consider the following book:
Bet 1: Mary bets stake x on B but conditionally upon Y.
i.e. she pays Peter x, and in return:
Peter pays her αx if both B and Y are achieved.
Peter pays her nothing if Y is achieved but not B.
Peter returns her x if Y is not achieved.
Bet 2: Mary bets stake y on B&Y, unconditionally.
i.e. she pays Peter y, and in return:
Peter pays her βy if both B and Y are achieved.
Peter pays her nothing if either B or Y is not
achieved.
Bet 3: Mary bets stake z on outcome Y, unconditionally.
i.e. she pays Peter z, and in return:
Peter pays her γz if Y is achieved.
Peter pays her nothing otherwise.
Then Mary’s net winnings, in the four possible situations, viz.
B&Y, –B&Y, B&–Y, –B&–Y, (using –B for “not B”…) are:
(α – 1)x + (β – 1)y + (γ – 1)z when B&Y is achieved
xy + (γ – 1)z when –B&Y is achieved
yz for either B&–Y or –B&–Y.
Now, if β αγ, Mary can choose:
x
y and
z , in which case all
these net winnings turn out to be + 1. (This is easy to check.)
So Mary has a Dutch-Book whenever α . But α =
if
and only if Π(B&Y)/Π(Y) is the rate accepted by Peter for the con-
ditional bet. In other words, Peter can be Dutch-Booked if he does
not use this rate. This is the very general result promised above.
Superficially, this result might seem to be little more than the
standard result for ontic conditional bets, but, despite the mis-
leading similarity in expression, the result here is very different,
and far broader. The standard result is in fact an extremely par-
ticular case of this general result, the particular case that pre-
sumes process 1 to be identical to process 2. The result pursued
in this paper for epistemic conditional bets is similarly a par-
ticular case of this more general result, that particular case
when a) process 2 takes place after process 1, and b) consists of
the release of knowledge about the outcome of process 1. The
evidential case is the case where again process 2 takes place
after process 1, where process 2 again involves the inspection
of the outcome of process 1, but where that inspection produces
outcomes that are experiences which fall short of supplying
knowledge about the outcomes of process 1.
Evidential conditional bets do not then require a special new
rule, but fit exactly the same generalized pattern as the ontic
and epistemic bets. Worse, we have seen that the particular rule
proposed by Jeffrey does in fact allow Mary to construct some
Dutch-Books. Whatever (dubious) virtues it might offer for
diachronic betting, it has nothing to offer for the synchronic
bets at issue here.
To give a concrete illustration of this claim that evidential
betting requires no special treatment, let us return to the exam-
ple introduced above (at the beginning of this discussion of
Jeffrey-conditioning), when the need for some expansion of the
rule for Peter’s choice of betting ratio was suggested by the
introduction of poor lighting. Paul’s “Tail”-utterance then ceased
to guarantee that there was a tail on the coin that had been drawn
at time τ, so bets conditional upon the “Tail”-utterance no longer
qualify as “epistemic” (in the sense contrasted with ontic bets
above). But we now know that Peter can be Dutch-Booked if he
accepts a bet on TT that is conditional upon the “Tail”-utterance,
at a rate that is not p(TT&“Tail”)/p(“Tail”).
Peter can calculate this safe betting ratio from his assess-
ments of the probabilities that each of a tail and a head will be
identified as a Tail. Suppose (to be concrete) that he assesses
these as 75% and 15% respectively. Then he will assess
p(“Tail”), the probability of the “Tail”-utterance, as 12(75%
+ 15%) or 45%. Similarly p(TT&“Tail”) will be 75% of 13
,
or 25%. So his safe betting ratio (for the conditional bet on TT,
that proceeds if and only if “Tail” is uttered) in these circum-
stances is 25%45% or 59
55.555...%.
To perform this calculation, Peter needed slightly more data
than is required to apply Jeffrey’s rule, which only used the
probability Peter would allocated to a tail if Paul made the
“Tail”-utterance. The data required for Jeffrey’s rule can be
calculated from that required for our rule, but not vice-versa, so
Jeffrey’s rule is more frugal than ours. Ours however is more
secure: every departure from it generates Dutch-Books.
In the example just given, a “Tail”-utterance leaves Peter
7590 certain that the coin has a tail on it, while a “Head”-
utterance leaves him 85110 certain that the coin has a head
on it. So according to Jeffrey’s rule, the updated probability for
two tails after hearing the “Tail”-utterance, will be 75 180 =
512 41.666...%. This differs considerably from our
55.555...%, but, if used by Peter, allows Mary to set up the
following Dutch-Book:
Bet 1: Mary bets stake $20 on TT but conditionally upon the
“Tail”-utterance.
i.e. she pays Peter $20, and in return:
Peter pays her $48 if “Tail” is uttered and TT is re-
vealed at time τ + 5, for by hypothesis the betting
ratio here is the Jeffrey-conditional 512.
Peter pays her $0 if “Tail” is uttered but TT is not
revealed.
Peter returns her $20 otherwise.
Bet 2: Peter bets stake $12 on TT&“Tail”, unconditionally.
i.e. he pays Mary $12; and in return:
Mary pays Peter $48 if “Tail” is uttered and TT is
revealed at time τ + 5, for Peter’s rate here is 14.
Mary pays Peter nothing if neither “Tail” is uttered
nor TT is revealed.
Bet 3: Mary bets stake $9 on the “Tail”-utterance.
Copyright © 2012 SciRes.
200
K. HUTCHISON
Copyright © 2012 SciRes. 201
the urn or Paul’s actual epistemic procedure, he becomes ex-
posed to (weak) Dutch books. So avoidance of a sure loss re-
quires Peter to do more than just allocate an appropriate condi-
tional probability. And it is surely impossible to establish that
Peter’s avoidance of one particular irrational bet protects him
from all others, right through his life.
i.e. she pays Peter $9; and in return:
Peter pays her $20 if “Tail” is uttered, for Peter’s
betting ratio here is now 45% or 9/20.
Peter pays her nothing otherwise.
Mary will now make a profit of $3 no matter what outcome
was produced in the original draw, or what utterance Paul
makes at τ + 3. This is clear in the tabulation of her earnings in
Table 3 below.
Yet some partial converses must surely hold, since we all do
believe that Peter can sometimes make conditional bets without
being Dutch-Booked. But it remains unclear what restrictions
need to be placed on such converses to make them valid. A
converse claim restricted to stronger books could well survive,
but any such claim would have to be carefully formulated, and I
do not know of any claims that are clearly valid.
An Inconclusive Conclusion: The Search for
a Converse
Having concluded, in the most general of our cases above, that
Peter can be Dutch-Booked if he accepts bets on an outcome B
of process 1 that are conditional on the outcome Y of process 2
at any rate other than Π(B&Y)/Π(Y), one is tempted to ask if
some reasonable converse of this result exists. Can we argue
that Peter is safe if he does use such a betting rate for each of
his conditional bets?
REFERENCES
De Finetti, B. (1974-1975). Theory of probability: A critical introduc-
tory treatment. (2 vols.) A. Machí, & A. Smith (Trans.), New York:
Wiley.
Gillies, D. (2000). Philosophical theories of probability. London:
Routledge.
Such a general result, however, remains in doubt, for it cer-
tainly fails with the characterizations of a Dutch-Book that
dominate the literature, those that do not explicitly embrace the
distinction (of p. 2) between weak and stronger books. For al-
though all the books that have faced Peter in the examples
above exploited seemingly irrational betting ratios, that is not
the only way Peter can face a sure loss. Simple error can do this
too. If Peter allocated subjective probabilities sufficiently in
compatible with such objective realities as the real contents of
Hacking, I. (1967). Slightly more realistic personal probability. Phi-
losophy of Science, 34, 311-325. doi:10.1086/288169
Harman, G. (1983). Problems with probabilistic semantics. In A. Oren-
stein & R. Stern (Eds.), Developments in semantics (pp. 242-245).
New York: Haven.
Howson, C. (1977). Bayesian rules of updating. Erkenntnis, 45, 195-
208.
Howson, C., & Urbach, P. (2006). Scientific reasoning: The Bayesian
approach (3rd ed.). Chicago, IL: Open Court.
Hutchison, K. (1999). What are conditional probabilities conditional
upon? Br i t i s h Journal for the Philosop h y o f S cience, 50, 665-695.
doi:10.1093/bjps/50.4.665
Table 3.
Mary’s winnings: counter-example to Jeffrey rule.
Jeffrey, R. (1983). The logic of decision (2nd ed.). Chicago, IL: Uni-
versity of Chicago Press.
Bet 1: TT/“Tail”
(512)
Bet 2: TT&“Tail”
(14)
Bet 3: “Tail”
(920)
Outcome Loss Gain Loss Gain Loss Gain Net Gain
HH&“Tail” $20 $0 $0 $12 $9 $20 $3
HH&“Head” $20 $20 $0 $12 $9 $0 $3
TT&“Tail” $20 $48 $48 $12 $9 $20 $3
TT&“Head” $20 $20 $0 $12 $9 $0 $3
HT&“Tail” $20 $0 $0 $12 $9 $20 $3
HT&“Head” $20 $20 $0 $12 $9 $0 $3
Skyrms, B. (1987). Dynamic coherence and probability kinematics.
Philosophy of Science, 54, 1-20. doi:10.1086/289350
Talbott, W. (2008). Bayesian epistemology (revision of Mar 26, 2008).
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. URL (last checked 9 Jun 2012).
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology-bayesian
Teller, P. (1973). Conditionalization and observation. Synthese, 26,
218-258. doi:10.1007/BF00873264
Weatherson, B. (2003). From classical to intuitionistic probability,
Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 44, 111-123.
doi:10.1305/ndjfl/1082637807.