Advances in Pure Mathematics
Vol.05 No.10(2015), Article ID:58868,41 pages
10.4236/apm.2015.510056
Non-Archimedean Analysis on the Extended Hyperreal Line and the Solution of Some Very Old Transcendence Conjectures over the Field
Jaykov Foukzon
Center for Mathematical Sciences, Israel Institute of Technology, Haifa, Israel
Email: jaykovfoukzon@list.ru
Copyright © 2015 by author and Scientific Research Publishing Inc.
This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution International License (CC BY).
Received 9 May 2015; accepted 15 August 2015; published 19 August 2015
ABSTRACT
In 1980 F. Wattenberg constructed the Dedekind completion of the Robinson non-archime- dean field
and established basic algebraic properties of
. In 1985 H. Gonshor estab- lished further fundamental properties of
. In [4] important construction of summation of countable sequence of Wattenberg numbers was proposed and corresponding basic properties of such summation were considered. In this paper the important applications of the Dedekind completion
in transcendental number theory were considered. Given any analytic function of one complex variable
we investigate the arithmetic nature of the values of
at transcendental points
. Main results are: 1) the both numbers
and
are irrational; 2) number
is transcendental. Nontrivial generalization of the Lindemann-Weierstrass theorem is obtained.
Keywords:
Non-Archimedean Analysis, Robinson Non-Archimedian Field, Dedekind Completion, Dedekind Hyperreals, Wattenberg Embeding, Gonshor Idempotent Theory, Gonshor Transfer
1. Introduction
In 1873 French mathematician, Charles Hermite, proved that is transcendental. Coming as it did 100 years after Euler had established the significance of
, this meant that the issue of transcendence was one mathematicians could not afford to ignore. Within 10 years of Hermite’s breakthrough, his techniques had been extended by Lindemann and used to add
to the list of known transcendental numbers. Mathematician then tried to prove that other numbers such as
and
are transcendental too, but these questions were too difficult and so no further examples emerged till today’s time. The transcendence of
has been proved in 1929 by A. O. Gel’fond.
Conjecture 1. Whether the both numbers and
are irrational.
Conjecture 2. Whether the numbers and
are algebraically independent.
However, the same question with and
has been answered:
Theorem. (Nesterenko, 1996 [1] ) The numbers and
are algebraically independent.
Throughout of 20-th century,a typical question: whether is a transcendental number for each algebraic number
has been investigated and answered many authors .Modern result in the case of entire functions satisfying a linear differential equation provides the strongest results, related with Siegel’s E-functions [1] [2] , ref [1] contains references to the subject before 1998, including Siegel
and
functions.
Theorem. (Siegel C. L.) Suppose that
(1.1)
Then is a transcendental number for each algebraic number
Let be an analytic function of one complex variable
Conjecture 3. Whether is an irrational number for given transcendental number
Conjecture 4. Whether is a transcendental number for given transcendental number
In this paper we investigate the arithmetic nature of the values of at transcendental points
Definition 1.1. Let be any real analytic function such that
(1.2)
We will call any function given by Equation (1.2) -analytic function and denoted by
Definition 1.2. [3] [4] . A transcendental number is called #-transcendental number over the field
, if there does not exist
-analytic function
such that
i.e. for every
-analytic function
the inequality
is satisfies.
Definition 1.3. [3] [4] . A transcendental number is called w-transcendental number over the field
, if
is not #-transcendental number over the field
, i.e. there exists
-analytic function
such that
Example. Number is transcendental but number
is not
-transcendental number over the field
as
(1) function is a
-analytic and
(2) i.e.
(1.3)
Main results are.
Theorem 1.1. [3] [4] . Number is #-transcendental over the field
.
From theorem 1.1 immediately follows.
Theorem 1.2. Number ee is transcendental.
Theorem 1.3. [3] [4] . The both numbers and
are irrational.
Theorem 1.4. For any number
is #-transcendental over the field
.
Theorem 1.5. [3] [4] . The both numbers and
are irrational.
Theorem 1.6. [3] [4] . Let be a polynomials with coefficients in
.
Assume that for any algebraic numbers over the field
,
form a complete set of the roots of
such that
(1.4)
and. Assume that
(1.5)
Then
(1.6)
2. Preliminaries. Short Outline of Dedekind Hyperreals and Gonshor Idempotent Theory
Let be the set of real numbers and
a nonstandard model of
[5] .
is not Dedekind complete.
For example, and
are bounded subsets of
which have no suprema or infima in
. Possible completion of the field
can be constructed by Dedekind sections [6] [7] . In [6] Wattenberg constructed the Dedekind completion of a nonstandard model of the real numbers and applied the construction to obtain certain kinds of special measures on the set of integers. Thus was established that the Dedekind com- pletion
of the field
is a structure of interest not for its own sake only and we establish further im- portant applications here. Important concept introduced by Gonshor [7] is that of the absorption number of an ele- ment
which, roughly speaking, measures the degree to which the cancellation law
fails for
.
2.1. The Dedekind Hyperreals
Definition 2.1. Let be a nonstandard model of
[5] and
the power set of
.
A Dedekind hyperreal is an ordered pair
that satisfies the next conditions:
1. 2.
3.
4. 5.
Compare the Definition 2.1 with original Wattenberg definition [6] ,(see [6] def.II.1).
Designation 2.1. Let We designate in this paper
Designation 2.2. Let We designate in this paper
Remark 2.1. The monad of is the set:
is denoted by
.
Supremum of is denoted by
. Supremum of
is denoted by
. Note that [6]
Let be a subset of
bounded above. Then
exists in
[6] .
Example 2.1. 1), 2)
Remark 2.2. Unfortunately the set inherits some but by no means all of the algebraic structure on
. For example,
is not a group with respect to addition since if
denotes the addition in
then:
Thus
is not even a ring but pseudo-ring only.
Definition 2.2. We define:
1. The additive identity (zero cut) often denoted by
or simply 0 is
2. The multiplicative identity often denoted by
or simply 1 is
Given two Dedekind hyperreal numbers and
we define:
3. Addition of
and
often denoted by
is
It is easy to see that for all
It is easy to see that is again a cut in
and
Another fundamental property of cut addition is associativity:
This follows from the corresponding property of.
4. The opposite of
, often denoted by
or simply by
, is
5. We say that the cut is positive if
or negative if
The absolute value of, denoted
, is
, if
and
if
6. If then multiplication
of
and
often denoted
is
In general, if
or
,
if
or
if
or
7. The cut order enjoys on the standard additional properties of:
(i) transitivity:
(ii) trichotomy: eizer or
but only one of the three
(iii) translation:
2.2. The Wattenberg Embeding into
Definition 2.3. [6] . Wattenberg hyperreal or #-hyperreal is a nonepty subset such that:
(i) For every and
(ii)
(iii) has no greatest element.
Definition 2.4. [6] . In paper [6] Wattenberg embed into
by following way:
If the corresponding element,
of
is
(2.1)
Remark 2.3. [6] . In paper [6] Wattenberg pointed out that condition (iii) above is included only to avoid nonuniqueness. Without it would be represented by both
and
Remark 2.4. [7] . However in paper [7] H. Gonshor pointed out that the definition (2.1) in Wattenberg paper [6] is technically incorrect. Note that Wattenberg [6] defines in general by
(2.2)
If i.e.
has no mininum, then there is no any problem with definitions (2.1) and (2.2). However if
for some
i.e.
then according to the latter definition (2.2)
(2.3)
whereas the definition of requires that:
(2.4)
but this is a contradiction.
Remark 2.5. Note that in the usual treatment of Dedekind cuts for the ordinary real numbers both of the latter sets are regarded as equivalent so that no serious problem arises [7] .
Remark 2.6. H. Gonshor [7] defines by
(2.5)
Definition 2.5. (Wattenberg embeding) We embed into
of the following way: (i) if
the corresponding element
of
is
(2.6)
and
(2.7)
or in the equivalent way,i.e. if the corresponding element
of
is
(2.8)
Thus if then
where
(2.9)
Such embeding into
Such embeding we will name Wattenberg embeding and to designate by
.
Lemma 2.1. [6] .
(i) Addition is commutative and associative in
.
(ii)
(iii)
Remark 2.7. Notice, here again something is lost going from to
since
does not imply
since
but
Lemma 2.2. [6] .
(i) a linear ordering on
often denoted
, which extends the usual ordering on
.
(ii)
(iii)
(iv) is dense in
. That is if
in
there is an
then
(v) Suppose that is bounded above then
exist in
.
(vi) Suppose that is bounded below then
exist in
.
Remark 2.8. Note that in general case In particular the formula for
given in [6] on the top of page 229 is not quite correct [7] , see Example 2.2. However by Lemma 2.2 (vi) this is no problem.
Example 2.2. [7] . The formula says
Let be the set
where
runs through the set of all positive numbers in
, then
However
Lemma 2.3. [6] .
(i) If then
(ii)
(iii)
(iv)
(v)
(vi)
Proof. (v) By (iv):
(1) Suppose now this means
(2) and therefore
(3)
(4) Note that: (since
and
imply
but this is a contradiction)
(5) Thus and therefore
(6) By similar reasoning one obtains:
(7) Note that: and therefore
Lemma 2.4. (i)
(ii)
Proof. (i) For the statement is clear. Suppose now without loss of generality
By Lemma 2.3. (iv):
(1) Suppose and therefore
but this means
(2) and therefore
(3)
(4) Note that: (since
and
imply
but this is a contradiction)
(5) Thus and therefore
(6) By similar reasoning one obtains:
(7) Note that: and therefore
(ii) Immediately follows from (i) by Lemma 2.3.
Definition 2.6. Suppose. The absolute value of
written
is defined as follows:
Definition 2.7. Suppose The product
, is defined as follows: Case (1)
:
(2.10)
Case (2)
Case (3)
(2.11)
Lemma 2.5. [6] . (i)
(ii) Multiplication is associative and commutative:
(2.12)
(iii) where
(iv)
(v) (2.13)
(vi) (2.14)
Lemma 2.6. Suppose and
Then
(2.15)
Proof. We choose now:
(1) such that:
(2) Note that
Then from (2) by Lemma 2.4. (ii) one obtains
(3) Therefore
(4)
(5) Then from (4) by Lemma 2.5. (v) one obtains
(6)
Then from (6) by Lemma 2.4. (ii) one obtains
(7)
Definition 2.8. Suppose then
is defined as follows:
(i)
(ii)
Lemma 2.7. [6] .
(i)
(ii)
(iii)
(iv)
(v)
(vi)
Lemma 2.8. [6] . Suppose that Then
Theorem 2.1. Suppose that is a non-empty subset of
which bounded from above, i.e.
exist and suppose that
Then
(2.16)
Proof. Let Then
is the smallest number such that, for any
Let
Since
for any
Hence
is bounded above by
Hence
has a supremum
Now we have to prove that
Since
is an upper bound for
and
is the smallest upper bound for
,
Now we repeat the argument above with the roles of
and
reversed. We know that
is the smallest number such that, for
any Since
it follows that
for any
But
Hence
is an upper bound for
. But
is a supremum for
. Hence
and
We have shown that
and also that
Thus
2.3. Absorption Numbers in
One of standard ways of defining the completion of involves restricting oneself to subsets, which have the following property
. It is well known that in this case we obtain a field. In fact the proof is essentially the same as the one used in the case of ordinary Dedekind cuts in the development of the standard real numbers,
, of course, does not have the above property because no infinitesimal works.This suggests the introduction of the concept of absorption part
of a number
for an element
of
which, roughly speaking, measures how much
departs from having the above property [7] .
Definition 2.9. [7] . Suppose then
(2.17)
Example 2.5.
(i)
(ii)
(iii)
(iv)
(v)
Lemma 2.9. [7] .
(i) and
(ii) and
Remark 2.9. By Lemma 2.7 may be regarded as an element of
by adding on all negative elements of
to
. Of course if the condition
in the definition of
is deleted we automatically get all the negative elements to be in
since
The reason for our
definition is that the real interest lies in the non-negative numbers. A technicality occurs if. We then identify
with 0. [
becomes
which by our early convention is not in
].
Remark 2.10. By Lemma 2.7(ii), is additive idempotent.
Lemma 2.10. [7] .
(i) is the maximum element
such that
(ii) for
(iii) If is positive and idempotent then
Lemma 2.11. [7] . Let satsify
Then the following are equivalent. In what follows assume
(i) is idempotent,
(ii)
(iii)
(iv)
(v) for all finite
Theorem 2.2. [7] .
Theorem 2.3. [7] .
Theorem 2.4. [7] .
(i)
(ii)
Theorem 2.5. [7] . Suppose then
(i)
(ii)
Theorem 2.6. [7] . Assume If
absorbs
then
absorbs
.
Theorem 2.7. [7] . Let Then the following are equivalent
(i) is an idempotent,
(ii)
(iii)
(iv) Let and
be two positive idempotents such that
Then
2.4. Gonshor Types of a with Given ab.p.(a).
Among elements of such that
one can distinguish two many different types following [7] .
Definition 2.10. [7] . Assume
(i) has type 1 if
(ii) has type 2 if
i.e.
has type 2 iff
does not have type 1.
(iii) has type 1A if
(iv) has type 2A if
2.5. Robinson Part of Absorption Number
Theorem 2.8. [6] . Suppose Then there is a unique standard
called Wattenberg stan- dard part of
and denoted by
such that:
(i)
(ii) implies
(iii) The map is continuous.
(iv)
(v)
(vi)
(vii) if
Theorem 2.9. [7] .
(i) has type 1 iff
has type 1A,
(ii) cannot have type 1 and type 1A simultaneously.
(iii) Suppose Then
has type 1 iff
has the form
for some
.
(iv) Suppose.
has type 1A iff
has the form
for some
.
(v) If then
has type 1 iff
has type 1.
(vi) If then
has type 2 iff either
or
has type 2.
Proof (iii) Let Then
. Since
(we chose
such that
and write
as
).
It is clear that works to show that
has type 1.
Conversely, suppose has type 1 and choose
such that:
Then we claim that:
By definition of certainly
. On the other hand by choice of
, every element of
has the form
with
.
Choose such that
then
.
Hence Therefore
Examples.
(i) has type 1 and therefore
has type 1A. Note that also
has type 2. (ii) Suppose
Then
has type 1 and therefore
has type 1A.
(ii) Suppose i.e.
has type 1 and therefore by Theorem 2.9
has the form
for some unique
Then, we define unique Robinson part
of absor- ption number
by formula
(2.18)
(iii) Suppose i.e.
has type 1A and therefore by Theorem 2.9
has the form
for some unique
Then we define unique. Robinson part
of absorption number
by formula
(2.19)
(iv) Suppose and
has type 1A, i.e.
has the form
for some
Then, we define Robinson part
of absorption number
by formula
(2.20)
(v) Suppose and
has type 1A, i.e.
has the form
for some
Then, we define Robinson part
of absorption number
by formula
(2.21)
Remark 2.11. Note that in general case, i.e. if Robinson part
of absorption number
is not unique.
Remark 2.12. Suppose and
has type 1 or type 1A. Then by definitions above one obtains the representation
2.6. The Pseudo-Ring of Wattenberg Hyperintegers
Lemma 2.12. [6] . Suppose that Then the following two conditions on
are equivalent:
(i)
(ii)
Definition 2.11. [6] . If satisfies the conditions mentioned above
is said to be the Wattenberg hyperinteger. The set of all Wattenberg hyperintegers is denoted by
Lemma 2.13. [6] . Suppose Then
(i)
(ii)
(iii)
The set of all positive Wattenberg hyperintegers is called the Wattenberg hypernaturals and is denoted by
Definition 2.12. Suppose that (i) (ii)
and (iii)
If and
satisfies these conditions then we say that
is divisible by
and we denote this by
Definition 2.13. Suppose that (i) and (ii) there exists
such that
(1) or
(2)
If satisfies the conditions mentioned above then we say that
is divisible by
and we denote this by
.
Theorem 2.10. (i) Let
be a prime hypernaturals such that (i)
. Let
be a Wattenberg hypernatural such that (i)
. Then
(ii) has type 1 iff
has type 1A,
(iii) cannot have type 1 and type 1A simultaneously.
(iv) Suppose Then
has type 1 iff
has the form
for some
(v) Suppose
has type 1A iff
has the form
for some
(vi) Suppose If
then
has type 1 iff
has type 1.
(vii) Suppose If
then
has type 2 iff either
or
has type 2.
Proof. (i) Immediately follows from definitions (2.12)-(2.13).
(iv) Let Then
. Since
(we chose
such that
and write a as
).
It is clear that a works to show that has type 1.
Conversely, suppose has type
and choose
such that:
Then we claim that:
By definition of certainly
. On the other hand by choice of a, every element of
has the form
with
.
Choose such that
then
.
Hence Therefore
2.7. The Integer Part Int.p(a) of Wattenberg Hyperreals
Definition 2.14. Suppose Then, we define
by formula
Obviously there are two possibilities:
1. A set has no greatest element. In this case valid only the
Property I:
Since implies
such that
But then
which implies
contradicting
2. A set has a greatest element,
In this case valid the
Property II: and obviously
Definition 2.15. Suppose Then, we define
by formula
Note that obviously:
2.8. External Sum of the Countable Infinite Series in
This subsection contains key definitions and properties of summ of countable sequence of Wattenberg hyperreals.
Definition 2. 16. [4] . Let be a countable sequence
such that
(i) or (ii)
or
(iii)
Then external sum (#-sum) of the corresponding countable sequence
is defined by
(2.22)
Theorem 2.11. (i) Let be a countable sequence
such that
and
Then
.
(ii) Let be a countable sequence
such that
and
Then
.
(iii) Let be a countable sequence
such that
and infinite series
absolutely converges to
in
Then
(2.23)
(iv) Let be a countable sequence
such that
and infinite series
absolutely converges to
in
Then
(2.24)
(v) Let be a countable sequence
such that
(1) and
(2)
Then
(2.25)
Proof. (i) Let and
Then obviously:
Thus there exists
such that (1)
(1)
Therefore from (1) by Robinson transfer one obtains (2)
(2)
Using now Wattenberg embedding from (2) we obtain (3)
(3)
From (3) one obtains (4)
(4)
Note that obviously
(5)
From (4) and (5) one obtains (6)
(6)
Thus (i) immediately from (6) and from definition of the idempotent.
Proof.(ii) Immediately from (i) by Lemma 2.3 (v).
Proof.(iii) Let. Then obviously:
and
. Thus
there exists
such that (1)
(1)
Therefore from (1) by Robinson transfer one obtains (2)
(2)
Using now Wattenberg embedding from (2) we obtain (3)
(3)
From (3) one obtains (4)
(4)
From (4) by Definition 2.16 (i) one obtains
(5)
Note that obviously
(6)
From (5)-(6) follows (7)
(7)
Thus Equation (2.23) immediately from (7) and from definition of the idempotent.
Proof.(iv) Immediately from (iii) by Lemma 2.3 (v).
Proof.(v) From Definition 2.16.(iii) and Equation (2.23)-Equation (2.24) by Theorem 2.7.(iii) one obtains
Theorem 2.12. Let be a countable sequence
such that
and infinite series
absolutely converges in
. Let
be external sum of the corresponding countable sequence
. Let
be a countable sequence where
is any rearrangement of terms of the sequence
. Then external sum
of the corresponding countable sequence
has the same value s as external sum of the countable sequence
, i.e.
Theorem 2.13. (i) Let be a countable sequence
such that (1)
(2) infinite series
absolutely converges to
in
and let
be external sum of the corresponding sequence
. Then for any
the equality is satisfied
(2.26)
(ii) Let be a countable sequence
such that (1)
(2) infinite series
absolutely converges to
in
and let
be external sum of the corresponding sequence
. Then for any
the equality is satisfied:
(2.27)
(iii) Let be a countable sequence
such that
(1)
(2) infinite series absolutely converges to
in
,
(3) infinite series absolutely converges to
in
.
Then the equality is satisfied:
(2.28)
Proof. (i) From Definition 2.16. (i) by Theorem 2.1, Theorem 2.11. (i) and Lemma (2.4) (ii) one obtains
(ii) Straightforward from Definition 2.16. (i) and Theorem 2.1, Theorem 2.11. (ii) and Lemma (2.4) (ii) one obtains
(iii) By Theorem 2.11. (iii) and Lemma (2.4). (ii) one obtains
But other side from (i) and (ii) follows
Definition 2.17. Let be a countable sequence
such that infinite series
absolutely converges in
to
We assume now that:
(i) there exists such that
or
(ii) there exists such that
or
(iii) there exists infinite sequence such that
(a) and infinite series
absolutely converges in
to
and
(b) there exists infinite sequence such that
and infinite series
absolutely converges in
to
.
Then: (i) external upper sum (#-upper sum) of the corresponding countable sequence is defined by
(2.29)
(ii) external lower sum (#-lower sum) of the corresponding countable sequence is defined by
(2.30)
Theorem 2.14. (1) Let be a countable sequence
such that infinite series
absolutely converges in
to
We assume now that:
(i) there exists such that
or
(ii) there exists such that
or
(iii) there exists infinite sequence such that
(a) and infinite series
absolutely converges in
to
and
(b) there exists infinite sequence such that
and infinite series
absolutely converges in
to
.
Then
(2.31)
and
(2.32)
Proof. (i), (ii), (iii) straightforward from definitions.
Theorem 2.15. (1) Let be a countable sequence
such that infinite series
absolutely converges in
to
We assume now that:
(i) there exists such that
or
(ii) there exists such that
or
(iii) there exists infinite sequence such that
(a) and infinite series
absolutely converges in
to
and
(b) there exists infinite sequence such that
and infinite series
absolutely converges in
to
.
Then for any the equalities is satisfied
(2.33)
and
(2.34)
Proof. Copy the proof of the Theorem 2.13.
Theorem 2.16. (1) Let be a countable sequence
such that infinite series
absolutely converges in
to
We assume now that:
(i) there exists such that
or
(ii) there exists such that
or
(iii) there exists infinite sequence such that
(a) and infinite series
absolutely converges in
to
and
(b) there exists infinite sequence such that
and infinite series
absolutely converges in
to
Then for any the equalities is satisfied
(2.35)
and
(2.36)
Proof. (1) From Equation (2.31) we obtain
(2.37)
From Equation (2.37) by Theorem 2.1 we obtain directly
(2.38)
(2) From Equation (2.32) we obtain
(2.39)
From Equation (2.39) by Theorem 2.1 we obtain directly
(2.40)
Remark 2.13. Note that we have proved Equation (2.35) and Equation (2.36) without any reference to the Lemma 2.4.
Definition 2.18. (i) Let be a countable sequence
such that
(2.41)
Then external countable upper sum (#-sum) of the countable sequence is defined by
(2.42)
In particular if where
the external countable upper sum (#-sum) of the countable sequence
is defined by
(2.43)
(ii) Let be a countable sequence
such that
(2.44)
Then external countable lower sum (#-sum) of the countable sequence is defined by
(2.45)
In particular if where
the external countable lower sum (#-sum) of the countable sequence
is defined by
(2.46)
Theorem 2.17. (i) Let be a countable sequence
such that valid the property (2.41). Then for any
the equality is satisfied
(2.47)
(ii) Let be a countable sequence
such that valid the property (2.44).
Then for any the equality is satisfied
(2.48)
Proof. Immediately from Definition 2.18 by Theorem 2.1.
Definition 2.19. Let be a countable sequence
such that infinite series
absolutely converges in
. Then external countable complex sum (#-sum) of the corresponding countable sequence
is defined by
(2.49)
correspondingly.
Note that any properties of this sum immediately follow from the properties of the real external sum.
Definition 2.20. (i) We define now Wattenberg complex plane by
with
. Thus for any
we obtain
, where
, (ii) for any
such that
we define
by
.
Theorem 2.18. Let be a countable sequence
such that infinite series
absolutely converges in
to
and
. Then
(i)
(ii)
2.9. Gonshor Transfer
Definition 2.21. [7] . Let.
Note that satisfies the usual axioms for a closure operator,i.e. if (i)
and
(ii) S has no maximum, then
Let f be a continuous strictly increasing function in each variable from a subset of into
. Specifically, we want the domain to be the cartesian product
where
for some
By Robin- son transfer f extends to a function
from the corresponding subset of
into
which is also strictly increasing in each variable and continuous in the Q topology (i.e.
and
range over arbitrary positive elements in
). We now extend
to
(2.50)
Definition 2.22. [7] . Let
then
(2.51)
Theorem 2.19. [7] . If f and g are functions of one variable then
(2.52)
Theorem 2.20. [7] . Let f be a function of two variables. Then for any and
(2.53)
Theorem 2.21. [7] . Let f and g be any two terms obtained by compositions of strictly increasing continuous functions possibly containing parameters in. Then any relation
or
valid in
extends to
i.e.
(2.54)
Remark 2.14. For any function we often write for short
instead of
.
Theorem 2.22. [7] . (1) For any
(2.55)
For any
(2.56)
(2) For any
(2.57)
(3) For any
(2.58)
(4) For any
(2.59)
Note that we must always beware of the restriction in the domain when it comes to multiplication.
Theorem 2.23. [7] . The map maps the set of additive idempotents onto the set of all multiplicative idempotents other than 0.
3. The Proof of the #-Transcendene of the Numbers
In this section we will prove the #-transcendence of the numbers Key idea of this proof reduction of the statement of
is #-transcendental number to equivalent statement in
by using pseudoring of Wattenberg hyperreals
[6] and Gonshor idempotent theory [7] . We obtain this reduction by three steps, see Subsections 3.2.1 - 3.2.3.
3.1. The Basic Definitions of the Shidlovsky Quantities
In this section we remind the basic definitions of the Shidlovsky quantities [8] . Let and
be the Shidlovsky quantities:
(3.1)
(3.2)
(3.3)
where this is any prime number. Using Equations (3.1)-(3.3.) by simple calculation one obtains:
(3.4)
and consequently
(3.5)
Lemma 3.1. [8] . Let p be a prime number. Then
Proof. ([8] , p. 128) By simple calculation one obtains the equality
(3.6)
where p is a prime. By using equality where
from Equations (3.1) and (3.6) one obtains
(3.7)
Thus
(3.8)
Lemma 3.2. [8] . Let p be a prime number. Then
.
Proof. ([8] , p. 128) By subsitution from Equation (3.3) one obtains
(3.9)
By using equality
(3.10)
and by subsitution Equation (3.10) into RHS of the Equation (3.9) one obtains
(3.11)
Lemma 3.3. [8] . (i) There exists sequences and
such that
(3.12)
where sequences and
does not depend on number p. (ii) For any
if
.
Proof. ([8] , p. 129) Obviously there exists sequences and
such that
and
does not depend on number p
(3.13)
and
(3.14)
Substitution inequalities (3.13)-(3.14) into RHS of the Equation (3.3) by simple calculation gives
(3.15)
Statement (i) follows from (3.15). Statement (ii) immediately follows from a statement (ii).
Lemma 3.4. [8] . For any and for any
such that
there exists
such that
(3.16)
Proof. From Equation (3.5) one obtains
(3.17)
From Equation (3.17) by using Lemma 3.3. (ii) one obtains (3.17).
Remark 3.1. We remind now the proof of the transcendence of following Shidlovsky proof is given in his book [8] .
Theorem 3.1. The number is transcendental.
Proof. ([8] , pp. 126-129) Suppose now that is an algebraic number; then it satisfies some relation of the form
(3.18)
where integers and where
Having substituted RHS of the Equation (3.5) into Equation (3.18) one obtains
(3.19)
From Equation (3.19) one obtains
(3.20)
We rewrite the Equation (3.20) for short in the form
(3.21)
We choose now the integers such that:
(3.22)
and. Note that
Thus one obtains
(3.23)
and therefore
(3.24)
By using Lemma 3.4 for any such that
we can choose a prime number
such that:
(3.25)
From (3.25) and Equation (3.21) we obtain
(3.26)
From (3.26) and Equation (3.24) one obtains the contradiction.This contradiction finalized the proof.
3.2. The Proof of the #-Transcendene of the Numbers. We Will Divide the Proof into Four Parts
3.2.1. Part I. The Robinson Transfer of the Shidlovsky Quantities
In this subsection we will replace using Robinson transfer the Shidlovsky quantities by corresponding nonstandard quantities
The properties of the nonstandard quantities
one obtains directly from the pro-
perties of the standard quantities using Robinson transfer principle [4] [5] .
1. Using Robinson transfer principle [4] [5] from Equation (3.8) one obtains directly
(3.27)
From Equation (3.11) using Robinson transfer principle one obtains:
(3.28)
Using Robinson transfer principle from inequality (3.15) one obtains:
(3.29)
Using Robinson transfer principle, from Equation (3.5) one obtains:
(3.30)
Lemma 3.5. Let, then for any
and for any
there exists
such that
(3.31)
Proof. From Equation (3.30) we obtain:
(3.32)
From Equation (3.32) and (3.29) we obtain (3.31).
3.2.2. Part II. The Wattenberg Imbedding into
In this subsection we will replace by using Wattenberg imbedding [6] and Gonshor transfer the nonstandard quantities and the nonstandard Shidlovsky quantities
by correspond- ing Wattenberg quantities
The properties of the Wattenberg quantities
one obtains directly from the properties of the co- rresponding nonstandard quantities
using Gonshor transfer principle [4] [7] .
1. By using Wattenberg imbedding from Equation (3.30) one obtains
(3.33)
2. By using Wattenberg imbedding and Gonshor transfer (see Subsection 2.9 Theorem 2.19) from Equation (3.27) one obtains
(3.34)
3. By using Wattenberg imbedding from Equation (3.28) one obtains
(3.35)
Lemma 3.6. Let then for any
and for any
there exists
such that
(3.36)
Proof. Inequality (3.36) immediately follows from inequality (3.31) by using Wattenberg imbedding and Gonshor transfer.
3.2.3. Part III. Reduction of the Statement of e Is #-Transcendental Number to Equivalent Statement in Using Gonshor Idempotent Theory
To prove that is #-transcendental number we must show that e is not w-transcendental, i.e., there does not exist real
-analytic function
with rational coefficients
such that
(3.37)
Suppose that e is w-transcendental, i.e., there exists an -analytic function
with rational coefficients:
(3.38)
such that the equality is satisfied:
(3.39)
In this subsection we obtain an reduction of the equality given by Equation (3.39) to equivalent equality given by Equation (3). The main tool of such reduction that external countable sum defined in Subsection 2.8.
Lemma 3.7. Let and
be the sum correspondingly
(3.40)
Then
Proof. Suppose there exists k such that Then from Equation (3.39) follows
There- fore by Theorem 3.1 one obtains the contradiction.
Remark 3.2. Note that from Equation (3.39) follows that in generel case there is a sequence such that
(3.41)
or there is a sequence such that
(3.42)
or both sequences and
with a property that is specified above exist.
Remark 3.3. We assume now for short but without loss of generelity that (3.41) is satisfied. Then from (3.41) by using Definition 2.17 and Theorem 2.14 (see Subsection 2.8) one obtains the equality [4]
(3.43)
Remark 3.4. Let and
be the upper external sum defined by
(3.44)
Note that from Equation (3.43)-Equation (3.44) follows that
(3.45)
Remark 3.5. Assume that and
. In this subsection we will write for a short
iff
absorbs
, i.e.
Lemma 3.8.
Proof. Suppose there exists such that
Then from Equation(3.45) one obtains
(3.46)
From Equation (3.46) by Theorem 2.11 follows that and therefore by Lemma 3.7 one obtains the contradiction.
Theorem 3.2. [4] The equality (3.43) is inconsistent.
Proof. Let us consider hypernatural number defined by countable sequence
(3.47)
From Equation (3.43) and Equation (3.47) one obtains
(3.48)
Remark 3.6. Note that from inequality (3.27) by Wattenberg transfer one obtains
(3.49)
Substitution Equation (3.30) into Equation (3.48) gives
(3.50)
Multiplying Equation (3.50) by Wattenberg hyperinteger by Theorem 2.13 (see subsec- tion 2.8) one obtains
(3.51)
By using inequality (3.49) for a given
we will choose infinite prime integer
such that:
(3.52)
Now using the inequality (3.49) we are free to choose a prime hyperinteger and
in the Equation (3.51) for a given
such that:
(3.53)
Hence from Equation (3.52) and Equation (3.53) we obtain
(3.54)
Therefore from Equations (3.51) and (3.54) by using definition (2.15) of the function given by Equation (2.20)-Equation (2.21) and corresponding basic property I (see Subsection 2.7) of the function
we obtain
(3.55)
From Equation (3.55) using basic property I of the function finally we obtain the main equality
(3.56)
We will choose now infinite prime integer in Equation (3.56)
such that
(3.57)
Hence from Equation (3.34) follows
(3.58)
Note that Using (3.57) and (3.58) one obtains:
(3.59)
Using Equation(3.35) one obtains
(3.60)
3.2.4. Part IV. The Proof of the Inconsistency of the Main Equality (3.56)
In this subsection we wil prove that main equality (3.56) is inconsistent. This prooff based on the Theorem 2.10 (v), see Subsection 2.6.
Lemma 3.9. The equality (3.56) under conditions (3.59)-(3.60) is inconsistent.
Proof. (I) Let us rewrite Equation (3.56) in the short form
(3.61)
where
(3.62)
From (3.59)-(3.60) follows that
(3.63)
Remark 3.7. Note that Otherwise we obtain that
But the other hand from Equation (3.61) follows that
But this is a contradic- tion. This contradiction completed the proof of the statement (I).
(II) Let and
be the external sum correspondingly
(3.64)
Note that from Equation (3.61) and Equation (3.64) follows that
(3.65)
Lemma 3.10. Under conditions (3.59)-(3.60)
(3.66)
and
(3.67)
Proof. First note that under conditions (3.59)-(3.60) one obtains
(3.68)
Suppose that there exists an such that
Then from Equation (3.65) one obtains
(3.69)
From Equation (3.69) by Theorem 2.17 one obtains
(3.70)
Thus
(3.71)
From Equation (3.71) by Theorem 2.11 follows that and therefore by Lemma 3.7 one obtains the contradiction. This contradiction finalized the proof of the Lemma 3.10.
Part (III)
Remark 3.8. (i) Note that from Equation (3.62) by Theorem 2.10 (v) follws that has the form
(3.72)
where
(3.73)
(ii) Substitution by Equation (3.72) into Equation (3.61) gives
(3.74)
Remark 3.9. Note that from (3.74) by definitions follows that
(3.75)
Remark 3.10. Note that from (3.73) by construction of the Wattenberg integer obviously follows that there exists some
such that
(3.76)
Therefore
(3.77)
Note that under conditions (3.59)-(3.60) and (3.73) obviously one obtains
(3.78)
From Equation(3.74) follows that
(3.79)
Therefore
(3.80)
From (3.78) follows that
(3.81)
Note that by Theorem 2.8 (see Subsection 2.5) and Formula (3.44) one otains
(3.82)
From Equation (3.81)-Equation (3.82) follows that
(3.83)
Thus
(3.84)
and therefore
(3.85)
But this is a contradiction. This contradiction completed the proof of the Lemma 3.9.
4. Generalized Shidlovsky Quantities
In this section we remind the basic definitions of the Shidlovsky quantities, see [8] pp. 132-134.
Theorem 4.1. [8] Let be a polynomials with coefficients in
. Assume that for any
algebraic numbers over the field
form a complete set of the roots of
such that
(4.1)
and Then:
(4.2)
Let be a polynomial such that
(4.3)
Let and
be the quantities [8] :
(4.4)
where in (4.4) we integrate in complex plane along line
see
Picture 1
.
(4.5)
where and where in (4.5) we integrate in complex plane
along line with initial point
and which are parallel to real axis of the complex plane
, see
Picture 1
.
(4.6)
where and where in (4.6) we integrate in complex plane
along contour
see
Picture 1
.
From Equation (4.3) one obtains
(4.7)
where Now from Equation (4.4) and Equation (4.7) using formula
Picture 1. Contour in complex plane
.
one obtains
(4.8)
where We choose now a prime p such that
Then from Equation (4.8) follows that
(4.9)
From Equation (4.3) and Equation (4.5) one obtains
(4.10)
where By change of the variable integration
in RHS of the Equation (4.10) we obtain
(4.11)
where Let us rewrite now Equation (4.11) in the following form
(4.12)
Let be a ring of the all algebraic integers. Note that [8]
(4.13)
Let us rewrite now Equation (4.12) in the following form
(4.14)
where From Equation (4.14) one obtains
(4.15)
The polinomial is a symmetric polynomial on any system
of variables
where
(4.16)
It well known that [8] and therefore
(4.17)
From Equation (4.15) and Equation (4.17) one obtains
(4.18)
Therefore
(4.19)
Let be a circle wth the centre at point
. We assume now that
. We will designate now
(4.20)
From Equation (4.6) and Equation (4.20) one obtains
(4.21)
where Note that
(4.22)
From (4.22) follows that for any there exists a prime number p such that
(4.23)
where From Equation (4.4)-Equation (4.6) follows
(4.24)
where Assume now that
(4.25)
Having substituted RHS of the Equation (4.24) into Equation (4.25) one obtains
(4.26)
From Equation (4.26) by using Equation (4.19) one obtains
(4.27)
We choose now a prime such that
and
Note that
and therefore from Equation (4.19) and Equation (4.27) one obtains the contradiction. This contradiction com- pleted the proof.
5. Generalized Lindemann-Weierstrass Theorem
Theorem 5.1. [4] Let be a polynomials with coefficients in
. Assume that for any
algebraic numbers over the field
form a complete set of the roots of
such that
(5.1)
and. We assume now that
(5.2)
Then
(5.3)
We will divide the proof into three parts.
Part I. The Robinson transfer
Let be a nonstandard polynomial such that
(5.4)
Let,
and
be the quantities:
(5.5)
where in (5.5) we integrate in nonstandard complex plane along line
see
Picture 1
.
(5.6)
where and where in (5.6) we integrate in nonstandard complex plane
along line with initial point
and which are parallel to real axis of the complex plane
, see
Picture 1
.
(5.7)
where and where in (5.7) we integrate in nonstandard complex plane
along contour
see
Picture 1
.
1. Using Robinson transfer principle [4] -[6] from Equation (5.5) and Equation (4.8) one obtains directly
(5.8)
where We choose now infinite prime
such that
(5.9)
2. Using Robinson transfer principle from Equation (5.6) and Equation (4.19) one obtains directly
(5.10)
and therefore
(5.11)
3. Using Robinson transfer principle from Equation (5.7) and Equation (4.21) one obtains directly
(5.12)
where Note that
there exists
(5.13)
4. From (5.13) follows that for any there exists an infinite prime
such that
(5.14)
where
5. From Equation (5.5)-Equation (5.7) we obtain
(5.15)
where
Part II. The Wattenberg imbedding into
1. By using Wattenberg imbedding and Gonshor transfer (see Subsection 2.8 Theorem 2.17) from Equation (5.8) one obtains
(5.16)
where We choose now an infinite prime
such that
(5.17)
2. By using Wattenberg imbedding and Gonshor transfer from Equation (5.10) one obtains directly
(5.18)
and therefore
(5.19)
3. By using Wattenberg imbedding and Gonshor transfer from Equation (5.14) one obtains directly
(5.20)
4. By using Wattenberg imbedding and Gonshor transfer from Equation (5.15) one obtains directly
(5.21)
where
Part III. Main equality
Remark 5.1. Note that in this subsection we often write for a short instead
For example we write
instead Equation (5.21).
Assumption 5.1. Let be a polynomials with coefficients in
. Assume that for any
algebraic numbers over the field
:
form a complete set of the roots of
such that
(5.22)
Note that from Assumption 5.1 follows that algebraic numbers over the field:
for any
form a complete set of the roots of
(5.23)
Assumption 5.2. We assume now that there exists a sequence
(5.24)
and rational number
(5.25)
such that
(5.26)
and
(5.27)
Assumption 5.3. We assume now for a short but without loss of generality that the all numbers
are real.
In this subsection we obtain an reduction of the equality given by Equation (5.27) in to some equivalent equality given by Equation (3) in
. The main tool of such reduction that external countable sum defined in Subsection 2.8.
Lemma 5.1. Let and
be the sum correspondingly
(5.28)
Then
Proof. Suppose there exists r such that Then from Equation (5.27) follows
There- fore by Theorem 4.1 one obtains the contradiction.
Remark 5.2. Note that from Equation (5.27) follows that in generel case there is a sequence such that
(5.29)
or there is a sequence such that
(5.30)
or both sequences and
with a property that is specified above exist.
Remark 5.3. We assume now for short but without loss of generelity that (5.29) is satisfied. Then from (5.29) by using Definition 2.17 and Theorem 2.14 (see Subsection 2.8) one obtains the equality [4]
(5.31)
Remark 5.4. Let and
be the upper external sum defined by
(5.32)
Note that from Equation (5.31)-Equation (5.32) follows that
(5.33)
Remark 5.5. Assume that and
In this subsection we will write for a short
iff
absorbs
, i.e.
Lemma 5.2.
Proof. Suppose there exists such that
Then from Equation (5.33) one obtains
(5.34)
From Equation (5.34) by Theorem 2.11 follows that and therefore by Lemma 5.1 one obtains the contradiction.
Theorem 5.2. [4] The equality (5.31) is inconsistent.
Proof. Let us considered hypernatural number defined by countable sequence
(5.35)
From Equation (5.31) and Equation (5.35) one obtains
(5.36)
where
(5.37)
Remark 5.6. Note that from inequality (5.12) by Gonshor transfer one obtains
(5.38)
Substitution Equation (5.21) into Equation (5.36) gives
(5.39)
Multiplying Equation (5.39) by Wattenberg hyperinteger by Theorem 2.13 (see sub- section 2.8) we obtain
(5.40)
By using inequality (5.38) for a given
we will choose infinite prime integer
such that:
(5.41)
Therefore from Equations (5.40) and (5.41) by using definition (2.15) of the function given by Equation (2.20)-Equation (2.21) and corresponding basic property I (see Subsection 2.7) of the function
we obtain
(5.42)
From Equation (5.42) finally we obtain the main equality
(5.43)
We will choose now infinite prime integer in Equation (3.56)
such that
(5.44)
Hence from Equation (5.16) follows
(5.45)
Note that Using (5.44) and (5.45) one obtains:
(5.46)
Using Equation (5.11) one obtains
(5.47)
Part IV. The proof of the inconsistency of the main equality (5.43)
In this subsection we wil prove that main equality (5.43) is inconsistent. This proof is based on the Theorem 2.10 (v), see Subsection 2.6.
Lemma 5.3. The equality (5.43) under conditions (5.46)-(5.47) is inconsistent.
Proof. (I) Let us rewrite Equation (5.43) in the short form
(5.48)
where
(5.49)
From (5.46)-(5.47) follows that
(5.50)
Remark 5.7. Note that Otherwise we obtain that
(5.51)
But the other hand from Equation (5.48) follows that
(5.52)
But this is a contradiction. This contradiction completed the proof of the statement (I).
(II) Let and
be the external sum correspondingly
(5.53)
Note that from Equation (5.43) and Equation (5.53) follows that
(5.54)
Lemma 5.4. Under conditions (5.46)-(5.47)
(5.55)
and
(5.56)
Proof. First note that under conditions (5.46)-(5.47) one obtains
(5.57)
Suppose that there exists such that
hen from Equation (5.54) one obtains
(5.58)
From Equation (5.58) by Theorem 2.17 one obtains
(5.59)
Thus
(5.60)
From Equation (5.60) by Theorem 2.11 follows that and therefore by Lemma 5.2 one obtains the contradiction. This contradiction finalized the proof of the Lemma 5.4.
(III)
Remark 5.8. (i) Note that from Equation (5.49) by Theorem 2.10 (v) follws that has the form
(5.61)
where
(5.62)
(ii) Substitution by Equation (5.61) into Equation (5.48) gives
(5.63)
Remark 5.9. Note that from (5.63) by definitions follows that
(5.64)
Remark 5.10. Note that from (5.62) by construction of the Wattenberg integer obviously follows that there exists some
such that
(5.65)
Therefore
(5.66)
Note that under conditions (5.46)-(5.47) and (5.66) obviously one obtains
(5.67)
From Equation (5.63) follows that
(5.68)
Therefore
(5.69)
From (5.69) follows that
(5.70)
Note that from (5.70) by Theorem 2.8 (see Subsection 2.5) and Formula (5.32) one otains
(5.71)
From Equation (5.70)-Equation (5.71) follows that
(5.72)
Thus
(5.73)
and therefore
(5.74)
But this is a contradiction. This contradiction completed the proof of the Lemma 5.3.
Remark 5.11. Note that by Definition 2.18 and Theorem 2.18 from Assumption 5.1 and Assumption 5.2 follows
Theorem 5.3.The equality (5.75) is inconsistent.
Proof. The proof of the Theorem 5.3 obviously copies in main details the proof of the Theorem 5.3.
Theorem 5.3 completed the proof of the main Theorem 1.6.
Cite this paper
JaykovFoukzon, (2015) Non-Archimedean Analysis on the Extended Hyperreal Line *Rd and the Solution of Some Very Old Transcendence Conjectures over the Field Q. Advances in Pure Mathematics,05,587-628. doi: 10.4236/apm.2015.510056
References
- 1. Nesterenko, Y.V. and Philippon, P., Eds. (2001) Introduction to Algebraic Independence Theory. Series: Lecture Notes in Mathematics, Vol. 1752. XIII, Springer Science & Business Media, 256 pp.
- 2. Waldschmidt, M. (2003) Algebraic Values of Analytic Functions. Journal of Computational and Applied Mathematics, 160, 323-333.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/S0377-0427(03)00637-X - 3. Foukzon, J. (2006) The Solution of one Very Old Problem in Transcendental Numbers Theory. Spring Central Sectional Meeting Notre Dame, IN, 8-9 April 2006, Meeting #1016 Preliminary Report.
http://www.ams.org/meetings/sectional/1016-11-8.pdf - 4. Foukzon, J. (2013) Non-Archimedean Analysis on the Extended Hyperreal Line *Rd and Some Transcendence Conjectures over Field Q and *Qω.
http://arxiv.org/abs/0907.0467 - 5. Goldblatt, R. (1998) Lectures on the Hyperreals. Springer-Verlag, New York.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4612-0615-6 - 6. Wattenberg, F. (1980) [0, ∞]-Valued, Translation Invariant Measures on and the Dedekind Completion of . Pacific Journal of Mathematics, 90, 223-247.
http://dx.doi.org/10.2140/pjm.1980.90.223 - 7. Gonshor, H. (1985) Remarks on the Dedekind Completion of a Nonstandard Model of the Reals. Pacific Journal of Mathematics, 118, 117-132.
http://dx.doi.org/10.2140/pjm.1985.118.117 - 8. Shidlovsky, A.B. (1982) Diophantine Approximations and Transcendental Numbers.
Moscow State University, Moscov. (In Russian).
http://en.bookfi.org/book/506517
http://bookre.org/reader?file=506517&pg=129