Journal of Quantum Information Science
Vol.04 No.04(2014), Article ID:52398,5 pages
10.4236/jqis.2014.44018

Reply to “Comments on ‘There Is No Axiomatic System for the Quantum Theory’”

Koji Nagata

13-3 West 6 South 27, Obihiro, Hokkaido, Japan

Email: ko_mi_na@yahoo.co.jp

Copyright © 2014 by author and Scientific Research Publishing Inc.

This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution International License (CC BY).

http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/

Received 13 October 2014; revised 15 November 2014; accepted 3 December 2014

ABSTRACT

Barros discusses that [Jose Acacio de Barros, Int. J. Theor. Phys. 50, 1828 (2011)] Nagata derives inconsistencies from quantum mechanics [K. Nagata, Int. J. Theor. Phys. 48, 3532 (2009)]. Barros considers that the inconsistencies do not come from quantum mechanics, but from extra assumptions about the reality of observables. Here we discuss the fact that there is a contradiction within the quantum theory. We discuss the fact that only one expected value in a spin-1/2 pure state rules out the reality of the observable. We do not accept extra assumptions about the reality of observables. We use the actually measured results of quantum measurements (raw data). We use a single Pauli observable. We stress that we can use the quantum theory even if we give up the axiomatic system for the quantum theory.

Keywords:

Quantum Measurement Theory, Quantum Computer, Formalism

1. Introduction

Barros discusses that [1] Nagata derives inconsistencies from quantum mechanics [2] . Barros considers that the inconsistencies do not come from quantum mechanics, but from extra assumptions about the reality of observables. More clearly, since quantum mechanics forbids the simultaneous measurements of non-commuting observables, as they do not commute, it does not allow us to simultaneously assign values to them. The contradiction does not come from quantum mechanics, but from the assumption that we can assign values to measurements that were not performed.

Here we discuss the fact that there is a contradiction within the quantum theory. We discuss the fact that only one expected value of a spin-1/2 pure state rules out the reality of the observable. We do not accept extra assumptions about the reality of observables. We use the actually measured results of quantum measurements (raw data). We use a single Pauli observable. We stress that we can use the quantum theory even if we give up the axiomatic system for the quantum theory.

On the other hand, the double-slit experiment [3] is an illustration of wave-particle duality. In it, a beam of particles (such as photons) travels through a barrier with two slits removed. If one puts a detector screen on the other side, the pattern of detected particles shows interference fringes characteristic of waves; however, the detector screen responds to particles. The system exhibits the behavior of both waves (interference patterns) and particles (dots on the screen).

If we modify this experiment so that one slit is closed, no interference pattern is observed. Thus, the state of both slits affects the final results. We can also arrange to have a minimally invasive detector at one of the slits to detect which slit the particle went through. When we do that, the interference pattern disappears [4] . An analysis of a two-atom double-slit experiment based on environment-induced measurements is reported [5] .

We assume implementation of the double-slit experiment. There is a detector just after each slit. Thus interference figure does not appear, and we do not consider such a pattern. The possible values of the result of measurements are (in unit). If a particle passes one side slit, then the value of the result of measurement is +1. If a particle passes through another slit, then the value of the result of measurement is −1. This model is an easy detector model for Pauli observable.

Projective measurement theory does not meet Deutsch’s algorithm [6] . In this reference, the expected values of the two spin observables and cannot be measured by using projective measurement theory. And new measurement theory covers the problem. Let us follow the argumentations. Assume a pure spin-1/2

state lying in the plane. We have from the wave functional analysis of quantum mechanics. On the other hand, we have if projective measurement theory is true. This fact cannot coexist with quantum formula. Hence the expected values of two spin ob-

servables and cannot be measured by using projective measurement theory. But, we have

when the new quantum measurement theory is true. The values of the result of quantum

measurements are. We consider whether an expected value of one spin observable can be measured by using projective measurement theory. So, we investigate the relation between an easy detector model for Pauli observable and projective measurement theory.

We consider whether projective measurement theory meets an easy detector model for Pauli observable. We try to implement double-slit experiment. There is a detector just after each slit. Thus interference figure does not appear, and we do not consider such a pattern. We assume that a source of spin-carrying particles emits them in a state, which can be described as an eigenvector of Pauli observable. We consider a single expected value of Pauli observable in the double-slit experiment. A wave function analysis says that the quantum expected value of it is zero. However, the quantum predictions within projective measurement theory cannot coexist with the value of the expected value of. Hence, such projective measurement theory does not meet the easy detector model.

At this stage we are in the following situation.

・ We cannot measure an expected value of a single spin observable in a state by using projective measurement theory.

2. There Is a Contradiction within the Quantum Theory by Using Joint Probability

First we discuss a contradiction within the quantum theory as follows [7] .

Matrix theory is not compatible with probability theory. Matrix theory has axioms. Probability theory has axioms. These have axioms without a contradiction. Can we construct axioms for matrix theory and probability theory without a contradiction?

Let us consider joint probability. is an observable. is an observable. a, b are actually measured results of quantum measurements in a quantum state, respectively. and are not commutative. Thus,

(1)

We consider as follows: First we measure observable and get as the actually measured result. And next we measure observable and get as the actually measured result. This joint event is different if we exchange to, in general. Hence

(2)

On the other hand, the joint probability is depictured in terms of conditional probabilities:

(3)

From axioms of probability theory, we have

(4)

We cannot assign truth value “1” for the proposition (2) and for the proposition (4), simultaneously. We are in a contradiction. We cannot construct axioms for matrix theory and probability theory without the contradiction. There is a contradiction within the quantum theory.

The first point is actually that, conventional Quantum Mechanics discussions typically do not employ conditional probabilities correctly if at all. This is the central issue with Bell’s analysis leading to the idea that Quantum Mechanics requires non-locality or irreality and wave packet collapse and what not!

3. Does Pauli Observable in a Quantum State Have a Counterpart in Physical Reality?

The two expected values of a spin-1/2 pure state and rule out the existence of probability space of von Neumann’s projective measurement [2] [6] .

In this section, we discuss the fact that only one expected value of a spin-1/2 pure state rules out the existence of probability space of von Neumann’s projective measurement.

We assume implementation of the double-slit experiment [3] . There is a detector just after each slit. Interference figure does not appear, and we do not consider such a pattern. Let be the Pauli vector. We assume that a source of spin-carrying particles emits them in a state, which can be described as an eigenvector of Pauli observable.

We consider a quantum expected value as

(5)

We introduce a hidden-variables theory for the quantum expected value of the Pauli observable. Then, the quantum expected value given in (5) can be

(6)

where is some hidden variable, is a probabilistic distribution, and is the predetermined “hidden” result of the measurement of the dichotomic observable. The possible values of are (in unit). If a particle passes one side slit, then the value of the result of measurement is +1. If a particle passes through another slit, then the value of the result of measurement is −1. It is von Neumann’s projective measurement for.

In what follows, we discuss the fact that we cannot assign the truth value “1” for the proposition (6). Assume the proposition (6) is true. We have the same proposition

(7)

An important note here is that the value of the right-hand-side of (6) is equal to the value of the right-hand- side of (7) because we only change a label.

We derive a necessary condition for the quantum expected value given in (6). We derive the possible value of the product of the quantum expected value and a delta sign. The quantum expected value is given in (6). We have

(8)

Here we use the fact

(9)

since the possible values of are. Hence we derive the following proposition if we assign the truth value “1” for a hidden-variables theory for the Pauli observable

(10)

We derive a necessary condition for the quantum expected value for the system in a pure spin-1/2 state given in (5). We derive the possible value of the product

(11)

is a delta sign. is the quantum expected value given in (5). We have the following proposition since

. (12)

We do not assign the truth value “1” for two propositions (10) and (12), simultaneously. We are in a contradiction. We have to give up a hidden-variables theory for the expected value of the Pauli observable. The measured observable in the state does not have a counterpart in physical reality.

4. There Is a Contradiction within the Quantum Theory by Using a Single Pauli Observable

Next we discuss the fact that there is a contradiction within the quantum theory by using a single Pauli observable [8] . In this case, there is no need to argue that observables under consideration are commuting or non-com- muting. Especially, we systematically describe our assertion based on more mathematical analysis using raw data (the actually measured results of quantum measurements). In this case, there is no need to argue the reality of observables. There exists raw data because we have seen it.

We consider the relation between double-slit experiment and projective measurement. We try to implement double-slit experiment. There is a detector just after each slit. Thus interference figure does not appear, and we do not consider such a pattern. The actually measured results of quantum measurements are (in unit). If a particle passes one side slit, then the value of the actually measured result of measurement is +1. If a particle passes through another slit, then the value of the actually measured result of measurement is −1.

4.1. A Wave Function Analysis

Let be the Pauli vector. We assume that a source of spin-carrying particles emits them in a state, which can be described as an eigenvector of Pauli observable. We consider a quantum expected value as

(13)

The above quantum expected value is zero if we consider only a wave function analysis.

We derive a necessary condition for the quantum expected value for the system in the pure spin-1/2 state given in (13). We derive the possible value of the product. is the quantum expected value given in (13). We derive the following proposition

(14)

4.2. Projective Measurement

On the other hand, a mean value admits projective measurement if it can be written as

(15)

where denotes a label and is the actually measured result of projective measurement of the Pauli observable. We assume the actually measured value of is (in unit).

Assume the quantum mean value with the system in an eigenvector of the Pauli observable admits projective measurement. One has the following proposition concerning projective measurement

(16)

We can assume as follows by Strong Law of Large Numbers1,

(17)

In what follows, we show that we cannot assign the truth value “1” for the proposition (16) concerning projective measurement.

Assume the proposition (16) is true. By changing a label into, we have the same quantum mean value as follows

(18)

An important note here is that the actually measured value of the right-hand-side of (16) is equal to the actually measured value of the right-hand-side of (18) because we only change the label. We have

(19)

Here is a delta sign. We use the following fact

(20)

Thus we derive a proposition concerning the quantum mean value under an assumption that projective measurement is true (in a spin-1/2 system), that is

(21)

From Strong Law of Large Numbers, we have

(22)

Hence we derive the following proposition concerning projective measurement

(23)

We do not assign the truth value “1” for two propositions (14) (concerning a wave function analysis) and (23) (concerning projective measurement), simultaneously. We are in a contradiction.

We cannot accept the validity of the proposition (16) (concerning projective measurement) if we assign the truth value “1” for the proposition (14) (concerning a wave function analysis). In other words, such projective measurement does not meet the detector model for spin observable. There is the contradiction within the quantum theory.

We note here that there is much nonsense in the Physics literature regarding the theoretical formality for Spin. The formalism is correct so long as only one dimension is under consideration---a restriction that is fully acceptable in view of the fact that to engage spin empirically a Magnetic (B) field is required and it can have only one direction at the point of interacting with a charge. All formal talk of the spin of a particle in both the and or directions at the same instant is vacuous for lack of B-fields in two directions at once.

5. Conclusion

In conclusions, Barros has discussed that Nagata has derived inconsistencies from quantum mechanics. Barros has considered that the inconsistencies do not come from quantum mechanics, but from extra assumptions about the reality of observables. Here we have discussed the fact that there is a contradiction within the quantum theory. We have discussed the fact that only one expected value of a spin-1/2 pure state rules out the reality of the observable. We do not have accepted extra assumptions about the reality of observables. We have used the actually measured results of quantum measurements (raw data). We have used a single Pauli observable. We have stressed that we can use the quantum theory even if we give up the axiomatic system for the quantum theory.

Acknowledgements

The author thanks Professor Tadao Nakamura.

References

  1. Acacio de Barros, J. (2011) Comments on “There Is No Axiomatic System for the Quantum Theory”. International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 50, 1828-1830. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10773-011-0696-z
  2. Nagata, K. (2009) There is No Axiomatic System for the Quantum Theory. International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 48, 3532-3536. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10773-009-0158-z
  3. Wikipedia (2014) Double-Slit Experiment. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Double-slit_experiment
  4. Wikipedia (2014) De Broglie-Bohm Theory.http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/De_Broglie%E2%80%93Bohm_theory
  5. Schon, C. and Beige, A. (2001) Analysis of a Two-Atom Double-Slit Experiment Based on Environment-Induced Measurements. Physical Review A, 64, Article ID: 023806. http://dx.doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevA.64.023806
  6. Nagata, K. and Nakamura, T. (2010) Can von Neumann’s Theory Meet the Deutsch-Jozsa Algorithm? International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 49, 162-170. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10773-009-0189-5
  7. Nagata, K. and Nakamura, T. (2013) An Additional Condition for Bell Experiments for Accepting Local Realistic Theories. Quantum Information Processing, 12, 3785-3789. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11128-013-0635-4
  8. Nagata, K. and Nakamura, T. (2013) Von Neumann’s Theory Does Not Meet Deutsch’s Algorithm. Precision Instrument and Mechanology, 2, 104.

NOTES

1In probability theory, the law of large numbers is a theorem that describes the result of performing the same experiment a large number of times. According to the law, the average of the results obtained from a large number of trials should be close to the expected value, and will tend to become closer as more trials are performed. The strong law of large numbers states that the sample average converges almost surely to the expected value.