American Journal of Operations Research
Vol. 2 No. 2 (2012) , Article ID: 19924 , 6 pages DOI:10.4236/ajor.2012.22017
The Theory of Membership Degree of Γ-Conclusion in Several n-Valued Logic Systems*
Department of Mathematics, Quanzhou Normal University, Quanzhou, China
Email: zjcqz@126.com
Received April 14, 2012; revised May 18, 2012; accepted May 30, 2012
Keywords: N-Valued Propositional Logic; Γ-Conclusion; Theory; Root; Membership Degree
ABSTRACT
Based on the analysis of the properties of Γ-conclusion by means of deduction theorems, completeness theorems and the theory of truth degree of formulas, the present papers introduces the concept of the membership degree of formulas A is a consequence of Γ (or Γ-conclusion) in Łukasiewicz n-valued propositional logic systems, n-valued propositional logic system and the
n-valued propositional logic systems. The condition and related calculations of formulas A being Γ-conclusion were discussed by extent method. At the same time, some properties of membership degree of formulas A is a Γ-conclusion were given. We provide its algorithm of the membership degree of formulas A is a Γ-conclusion by the constructions of theory root.
1. Introduction
Fuzzy logic is the theoretical foundation of fuzzy control. Spurred by the success in its applications, especially in fuzzy control, fuzzy logic has aroused the interest of many famous scholars, a series of important results have been created in documents [1-5]. For the sake of reasoning, we have to choose a subset of well-formed formulas, which can reflect come essential properties, as the axioms of the logical system and we then deduce the so-called
-conclusion through some reasonable inference rules [6-9]. So, a natural question then arises: how to judge whether or not a general formula
is a conclusion of a given theory
, or to what extend the formula
is a conclusion of
? It is basic problem to judge one thing belong to one kind in artificial intelligence. As is well known, human reasoning is approximate rather than precise in nature. we basic starting point is to establish graded version of basic logical notions. In order to establish a solid foundation for fuzzy reasoning, professor G. J. Wang proposed the concept of root of theory [3], J. C. Zhang proposed the concept of generalized root of theory [10,11], in propositional logic systems. The graded description and properties of formulas
being
-conclusion were discussed. And provide its algorithm of membership degree of formulas A is a
-conclusion, by the constructions of theory root in the above-mentioned logic systems.
2. Preliminaries
It is well known that different implication operators and valuation lattices (i.e., the set of truth degrees for logic) determine different logic systems (see [12]). Here valuation lattices is
and three popularly used implication operators and the correspond ing t-norms defined as follows:
These three implication operators and
are called Łukasiewicz implication operator
, Gödel implication operator
, and the
-implication operator
, respectively. The t-norm, which corresponds to
-implication operator
, is called also Nilpotent Minimumtnorm [6]. If we fix a t-norm
above we then fix a propositional calculus (whose set of truth values is
):
is taken for the truth function of the strong conjunction &, the residuum
of
becomes the truth function of the implication operator and R(.,0) is the truth function of the negation. In more details, we have the following definitions.
Definition 1 [7,8]. The propositional calculus given by a t-norm
has the set
of propositional variables
and connectives
. The set
of well-formed formulas in
is defined inductively as follows: each propositional variable is a formula; if
,
are formulas, then
,
and
are all formulas.
Definition 2 [8,9,13]. The formal deductive systems of given by
corresponding to
and
, are called Łukasiewicz n-valued logic systems
,
n-valued logic systems
, and the
nvalued logic systems
, respectively.
Define in the above-mentioned logic systems
(1)
and in the corresponding algebras
(2)
where is the t-norm defined on
.
Remark 1. It is easy to verify that the following assertions are true:
(1) in,
for every
.
(2) in,
for every
and
.
(3) in
, for every
.
Definition 3 [7,8]. (1) A homomorphism of type
from
into the valuation lattice
, i.e.
, is called an R-valuation of
. The set of all R-valuations will be denoted by
.
(2) A formula is called a tautology w.r.t.
if
holds.
Remark 2 [8,13]. It is not difficult to verify in the above-mentioned three logic systems that , and
for every valuation
. Moreover, one can check in
and
that
and
are logically equivalent.
Definition 4 [8]. Assume that is a formula generated by propositional variables
through connectives
. Substitute
for
in
and keep the logic connectives in
unchanged but explain them as the corresponding operators defined on the valuation lattice
. The we get a function
and call
the truth degree function of
.
Definition 5 [7,8]. (1) A subset of is called a theory.
(2) Let be a theory,
. A deduction of
from
, in symbols,
, is a finite sequence of formulas
such that for each
is an axiom of
, or
, or there are
such that
follows from
and
by MP. Equivalently, we say that
is a conclusion of
(or
-conclusion). The set of all conclusions of
is denoted by
. By a proof of
we shall henceforth mean a deduction of
from the empty set. We shall also write
in place of
and call
a theorem.
It is easy for the reader to check the following Proposition 1.
Proposition 1. Let be a theory and
If
then there exist a finite subset of
say,
such that
.
Theorem 1 (Generalized deduction theorems) [7, 8,12]. Suppose that is a theory,
, then
(1) in ,
iff
s. t.
.
(2) in,
iff
.
(3) in,
iff
.
Definition 6 [8,13]. Suppose that is a formula of
containing m atomic formulas
, and
be the truth degree function of
. Then
is called the truth degree of, where
is the cardinal of set
.
Theorem 2. Suppose that and
, then in
and
iff
is a tautology i.e.,
.
Proof. Assume that. Since
then
. By definite,
, thus
i.e.,
,
, then
is a tautology. Conversely, assume that A is a tautology i.e.,
, then
, so
. This completes the proof.
Theorem 3 [8]. Suppose that, then in
,
iff
is a tautology, i.e.,
.
Theorem 4. Suppose that. If for every
, then
.
Proof. Suppose that and
are all a formulas of
containing
atomic formulas
, it follows from
that
and
hence
.
It is easy to verify that
then.
3. Properties of the Roots of Theories
Definition 7 [3]. Suppose that is a theory,
. If for every
we have
, then
is called the root of
.
Theorem 5. Suppose that is a finite theory, say
, then
(1) in
is a root of
;
(2) in,
is a root of
;
(3) in,
is a root of
.
Proof. (1) It following form references [4] that, for every
, there exist
such that
by Theorem 1. It is easy to check that
by Remark 1, it following from
that
where
, thus
by Hypothetical, this shows that
is a root of
.
(2) It following form references [4] that , for every
, it following from Theorem 1 that
, since
and
are provably equivalent, and so is
. This shows
is a root of
.
(3) It following from references [4] that for every
, we get
by Theorem 1, it is easy to verify that
and
are provably equivalent, hence
and
are provably equivalent, and so is
. This shows that
is a root of
.
4. Membership Degree of Formulas A Is Γ-Conclusion
In following, let us first take an analysis on the conditions of formulas A is a -conclusion in
. Suppose that
is a theory and A is a
-conclusion , it follows from Proposition 1 and Theorem 1 that there exit a finite string of formulas
and
such that
holds, i.e., the formula
is a theorem of
, let
, hence
is a tautology, it follows from Theorem 2 that
. Conversely, if there exist a
-conclusion
such that
, then following from Theorem 2 that
is a tautology, thus
is a theorem of
, i.e.,
holds and
, we have that
by MP, i.e.,
is a
-conclusion. Moreover, the larger the membership degree of such formulas are, the more closer A is to be
-conclusion. Hence it is natural and reasonable for us using the supremum of truth degree of all formulas with the form
where
to measure A is a
-conclusion.
Definition 8. Suppose that is a theory,
. Define
then is called the membership degree of formulas A is a
-conclusion.
It is easy to verify that and following Proposition 2 by Definition 8.
Proposition 2. In,
and
If A is a
-conclusion, then
.
Theorem 6. In,
and
, if
is a finite theory, say
, then A is a
-conclusion iff
.
Proof. The necessity part by proposition 2, it is only necessary to prove the sufficiency. Let. For every number
there exist a formulas
such that
by Definition 8.
(1) In, it follows from Theorem 5 that
is a root of
and
hold. Hence for every
we have
it follows from properties of implication operators that
, since
is arbitrary, we have
, thus
is a tautology, and
is a theorem , together with the result
, then
by MP, i.e.,
(2) In, notice that
is a root of
by Theorem 5, hence the proof of (2) is similar to that the proof of (1) and so is omitted.
(3) In, notice that
is a root of
by Theorem 5, hence the proof of (2) is similar to that the proof of (1). In fact
is a theorem by Definition 7, hence
we have
and
, thus
,
holds, then
is a theorem , together with the result
we have
by MP. The proof is completed.
Theorem 7. Suppose that, then
(1) in,
;
(2) in,
;
(3) in,
.
Proof. (1) Since is a root of
by Theorem 5, hence for every
we have
. Thus for every
,
, and
holds, then
by Theorem 4. It follows from
that
i.e.,
.
(2) Notice that in,
is a root of
by Theorem 5, the proof of (2) is similar to that the proof of (1) and so is omitted.
(3) Notice that in,
is a root of
by Theorem 5, the proof of (2) is similar to that the proof of (1) and so is omitted.
Theorem 8. Suppose that is a infinite theory. Then
(1) in,
;
(2) ,
;
(3) in,
.
Proof. (1) For every, it following from Proposition 1 that there exist a finite string of formulas
such that
It follows from Theorem 1 that
is a theorem, hence
is a tautology by completeness theorem, and for every
,
, we have
by Theorem 4.
It following form references [14] that , then
.
(2) Notice that in,
by Remark 1, the Proof of (2) is similar to that the Proof of (1) and so is omitted.
(3) Notice that in,
and
is Provably equivalent, the Proof of (3) is similar to that the Proof of (1) and so is omitted.
Theorem 9. Suppose that is a theory,
and
, then
Proof. (1) If we get
, then
(2) If we get
and
, for any given positive number
such that
and
there exists formulas
such that
and
. It follows from properties of Regular implication operators that
and
It is easy to verify that
and
are provably equivalent (i.e., logically equivalent), hence
. It follows from the theory of truth degrees of formulas and
that
.
Bucas and
are provably equivalent (i.e., logically equivalent), hence
, it is easy to verify that
then
by the definition of the membership degree of formulas.
Example 1. Suppose that In
,
and
, compute
respectively.
Solution. (1) In, assume that
Since
and
thus
and
We have and
hence
then
.
(2) In, assume that
Since
, and
thus
then
then.
(3) In, assume that
Since
, and
thus
then
Example 2. Suppose that
, in
, compute
Solution. (1) Assume that Since
, and
thus, then p2
is a -conclusion.
REFERENCES
- H. W. Liu and G. J. Wang, “Unified Forms of Fully Implicational Restriction Methods for Fuzzy Reasoning,” Information Sciences, Vol. 177, No. 3, 2007, pp. 956-966. doi:10.1016/j.ins.2006.08.012
- J. Pavelka, “On Fuzzy Logic II-Enriched Residuated Lattices and Semantics of Propositional Calculi,” Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, Vol. 25, 2011, pp. 119-134.
- G. J. Wang and H. Wang, “Non-Fuzzy Versions of Fuzzy Reasoning in Classical Logic,” Information Sciences, Vol. 138, No. 1-4, 2011, pp. 211-236. doi:10.1016/S0020-0255(01)00131-1
- G. J. Wang, “On the Logic Foundation of Fuzzy Reasoning,” Information Sciences, Vol. 117, No. 1-2, 1999, pp. 47-88. doi:10.1016/S0020-0255(98)10103-2
- M. S. Ying, “Compactness, the Löwenheim-Skolem Property and the Direct Product of Lattices of Truth Values,” Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, Vol. 38, 1992, pp. 521-524.
- F. Esteva and L. Godo, “Monoidal t-Norm Based Logic: Towards a Logic for Left-Continuous t-Norms,” Fuzzy Set and Systems, Vol. 124, No. 3, 2001, pp. 271-288. doi:10.1016/S0165-0114(01)00098-7
- P. Hájek, “Metamathematics of Fuzzy Logic,” Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, 1998.
- G. J. Wang and H. J. Zhou, “Introduction to Mathematical Logic and Resolution Principle,” 2nd Edition, Science in China Press, Beijing, 2006 (in Chinese).
- G. J. Wang, “A Formal Deductive System for Fuzzy Propositional Calculus,” Chinese Science Bulletin, Vol. 42, No. 14, 1997, pp. 1521-1525.
- J. C. Zhang, “Some Properties of the Roots of Theories in Propositional Logic Systems,” Computers and Mathematics with Applications, Vol. 55, No. 9, 2008, pp. 2086- 2093. doi:10.1016/j.camwa.2007.08.035
- J. C. Zhang and X. Y. Yang, “Some Properties of Fuzzy Reasoning in Propositional Fuzzy Logic Systems,” Information Sciences, Vol. 180, No. 23, 2010, pp. 4661- 4671. doi:10.1016/j.ins.2010.07.035
- S. Gottwald, “A Treatise on Many-Valued Logics, Studies in Logic and Computation,” Research Studies Press, Baldock, 2001.
- G. J. Wang, “Theory of Non-Classical Mathematical Logic and Approximate Reasoning,” Science in China Press, Beijing, 2000.
- D. Dubois, J. Lang and H. Prade, “Fuzzy Set in Approximate Reasoning,” Fuzzy Sets and Systems, Vol. 40, No. 1, 1991, pp. 143-244. doi:10.1016/0165-0114(91)90050-Z
NOTES
*The work was supported by the Science and Technology Item of the Education Department of Fujian Province of China (No. 2010JA10235).