Journal of Biosciences and Medicines
Vol.06 No.01(2018), Article ID:82031,26 pages
10.4236/jbm.2018.61008

Epstein Bar Virus―The Cause of Hodgkin’s Lymphoma

Ilija Barukčić

Internist: Horandstrase, DE-26441, Jever, Germany

Copyright © 2018 by author and Scientific Research Publishing Inc.

This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution International License (CC BY 4.0).

http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/

Received: November 27, 2017; Accepted: January 23, 2018; Published: January 26, 2018

ABSTRACT

Objective: Epstein-Barr virus (EBV), a herpes virus which persists in memory B cells in the peripheral blood for the lifetime of a person, is accused to be associated with several malignancies. Hodgkin’s lymphoma (HL) has long been suspected to have an Epstein-Barr virus infection as a causal agent. Some recent studies identified an EBV latent infection to a high degree in Hodgkin’s lymphoma. However, despite intensive study, the role of Epstein-Barr virus infection in Hodgkin lymphoma remains enigmatic. Methods: To explore the cause-effect relationship between EBV and HL and so to understand the role of EBV in HL etiology more clearly, a systematic review and re-analysis of studies published is performed. The method of the conditio per quam relationship was used to proof the hypothesis if Epstein-Barr virus infection (DNA) in human lymph nodes is present then Hodgkin lymphoma is present too. The mathematical formula of the causal relationship k was used to proof the hypothesis, whether there is a cause effect relationship between an Epstein-Barr virus infection (EBV DNA) and Hodgkin lymphoma. Significance was indicated by a p-value of less than 0.05. Result: The data analyzed support the Null-hypotheses that if Epstein-Barr virus infection (EBV DNA) is present in human lymph nodes then Hodgkin lymphoma is present too. In the same respect, the studies analyzed provide highly significant evidence that Epstein-Barr virus the cause of Hodgkin lymphoma. Conclusion: The findings of this study suggest that Epstein-Barr virus is the cause of Hodgkin’s lymphoma besides of the complexity of Hodgkin’s disease.

Keywords:

Epstein-Barr Virus, Hodgkin’s Lymphoma, Causal Relationship

1. Introduction

In 1964, Epstein [1] , Barr, and Achong discovered viral particles in lymphoblasts isolated from a patient with Burkitt’s lymphoma, meanwhile known as Epstein-Bar virus. Historically, EBV was the first human cancer virus to be described. This fundamental discovery paved the way for further investigations into the oncogenic potential of viruses. Epstein-Barr virus (EBV), also called human herpes virus 4 (HHV-4), is a ubiquitous double-stranded DNA gamma-1 human herpes virus which infects more than 90% of the world population. EBV can be transmitted from person to person in several ways. After the primary infection, EBV persists for life [2] in memory B cells in the peripheral blood of human host while well controlled by host’s immune system. Primarily resting memory B cells in peripheral blood are the infected cells which provide a permanent reservoir for the virus. Similar to other herpes viruses, an EBV reactivation [3] reflected by aberrant IgG, IgM, IgA antibody responses can occur. The spectrum of diseases which are associated with Epstein-Barr virus includes Burkitt’s [1] lymphoma (BL), nasopharyngeal [4] carcinoma, infectious mononucleosis [5] (IM), Hodgkin’s [6] disease and many other too. Hodgkin lymphoma (HL) itself, named after the English physician Thomas Hodgkin [7] , who first described this malignancy in 1832, is characterized by the presence of a minority of malignant Hodgkin/Reed-Sternberg (HRS) cells and the disruption of normal lymph node [8] architecture. The Sternberg-Reed cells [9] [10] which are pathognomonic for Hodgkin lymphoma (HL) were described over a century ago and origin from B lymphocytes [11] . Several environmental factors have been discussed in the etiology of Hodgkin’s disease [12] . Among them viruses like herpes simplex, cytomegalovirus [13] or EBV [14] . The detection of raised antibody titers to EBV [15] antigens in HL patients compared with other lymphoma patients provided the first evidence that EBV might be involved in the pathogenesis of HL. Finally, Weiss et al. [16] examined for the presence of Epstein-Barr virus (EBV) in tissue specimens of Hodgkin’s disease and were able to detect EBV DNA in Hodgkin’s disease.

2. Material and Methods

Hodgkin lymphoma (HL) is a deadly disease too. Identifying the cause of Hodgkin’s lymphoma has the potential to spare a lot of lives.

2.1. Study of Veronique Dinad et al. (2007)

Dinand et al. [17] conducted a case control study to investigate the prevalence and significance of Epstein-Barr virus in Hodgkin’s and Reed-Sternberg cells in children. EBV detection was performed by immunohistochemistry (IHC) and in situ hybridization (ISH). Dinand et al. [17] detected EBV by ISH in 126/135 (93.3%) out of 135 cases, and in none 0/25 (0%) of the control lymph node examined. The data as obtained 2007 by Dinand et al. are presented by the 2 by 2-table (Table 1).

Novel and modern laboratory techniques [18] such as Southern Blot hybridization, Immunohistochemistry (IHC), In-situ hybridization (ISH), Fluorescent

Table 1. Epstein-Barr virus (EBV) and Hodgkin’s lymphoma according to Dinand et al. (2007).

ISH (FISH), RNA in situ hybridization (RNA ISH), Polymerase chain reaction (PCR), Nested PCR, Quantitative polymerase chain reaction (QPCR) have fueled us to change our understanding of the pathogenesis of cancer development. Immunohistochemistry (IHC), introduced by Coons [19] in 1941, is useful in distinguishing between benign and malignant cell populations. Still, a cross-reactivity with cellular proteins is possible which has impact on the specifity of this method. In situ hybridization (ISH) is a fundamental technique, described in the year 1969 by Joseph G. Gall [20] is used commonly for research purposes especially to distinguish virus in tumor cells from virus in non-tumor cells. Despite of numerous advantages, the use of the ISH technique is associated with certain and severe limitations. The skill of the personnel involved in performing and interpreting ISH has influence on the reproducibility and accuracy of this procedure. In situ hybridization (ISH) even if regarded as superior to PCR depend on the target used which has impact on the sensitivity and specificity of this methods. Even the In situ hybridization (ISH) can produce false positive or false negative results.

2.2. Study of Veronique Dinad et al. (2015)

Veronique Dinand et al. [21] conducted a study to measure circulating EBV DNA in 30 children with Hodgkin lymphoma (HL) and in 70 controls, with prospective follow-up of the Hodgkin lymphoma cohort (2007-2012). Over the same time period, a cohort study monitored the HL cohort’s response to therapy, EBV load and long-term remission status. Pre-treatment quantitative EBV-DNA PCR was positive in 19 out of 30 children with Hodgkin lymphoma cases while all 70 controls were tested EBV quantitative PCR negative. The highest EBV load was 430,000 copies/mL. Out of 19 quantitative EBV-DNA PCR was positive children, one died of advanced disease before starting chemotherapy. The data as obtained 2015 by Dinand et al. are presented by the 2 by 2-table (Table 2).

2.3. Statistical Analysis

All statistical analyses were performed with Microsoft Excel version 14.0.7166.5000 (32-Bit) software (Microsoft GmbH, Munich, Germany).

2.3.1. Bernoulli Trials

Among some discrete distributions like the hypergeometric distribution, the

Table 2. Epstein-Barr virus (EBV) and Hodgkin’s lymphoma according to Dinand et al. (2015).

Poisson distribution et cetera the binomial distribution is of special interest. Sometimes, the binomial distribution is called the Bernoulli distribution in honor of the Swiss mathematician Jakob Bernoulli (1654 - 1705), who derived the same. Bernoulli trials are an essential part of the Bernoulli distribution. Thus far, let us assume two fair coins named as 0Wt and as RUt. In our model, heads of such a coin are considered as success T (i.e. true) and labeled as +1 while tails may be considered as failure F (i.e. false) and are labeled as +0. Such a coin is called a Bernoulli-Boole coin. The probability of success of RUt at one single Bernoulli trial t is denoted as

p ( U R t = + 1 ) p ( U R t ) (1)

The probability of failure of RUt at one single Bernoulli trial t is denoted as

p ( U R t = + 0 ) p ( U _ R t ) 1 p ( U R t ) (2)

Furthermore, no matter how many times an experiment is repeated, let the probability of a head or the tail remain the same. The trials are independent which implies that no matter how many times an experiment is repeated, the probability of a single event at a single trial remain the same. Repeated independent trials which are determined by the characteristic that there are always only two possible outcomes, either +1 or +0 and that the probability of an event (outcome) remain the same at each single trial for all trials are called Bernoulli trials. The definition of Bernoulli trials provides a theoretical model which is of further use. However, in many practical applications, we may by confronted by circumstances which may be considered as approximately satisfying Bernoulli trials. Thus far, let us perform an experiment of tossing two fair coins simultaneously. Suppose two fair coins are tossed twice. Then there are 22 = 4 possible outcomes (the sample space), which may be shown as

( [ U R t = + 1 ] , [ W 0 t = + 1 ] ) , ( [ U R t = + 1 ] , [ W _ 0 t = + 0 ] ) , ( [ U _ R t = + 0 , W 0 t = + 1 ] ) , ( [ U _ R t = + 0 , W _ 0 t = + 0 ] )

This may also be shown as a 2-dimensional sample space in the form of a contingency table (Table 3).

In the following, the contingency table is defined more precisely (Table 4).

In general it is ( a + c ) = W 0 t , ( a + b ) = U R t , ( c + d ) = W _ 0 t , ( b + d ) = U _ R t and a + b + c + d = N = W R t . Equally, it is W 0 t + W _ 0 t = U R t + U _ R t = W R t = N . Thus far, if one fair coin is tossed n times, we have n repeated Bernoulli trials

Table 3. The sample space of a contingency table.

Table 4. The sample space of a contingency table.

and an n dimensional sample space with 2n sample points is generated. In general, when given n Bernoulli trials with k successes, the probability to obtain exactly k successes in n Bernoulli trials is given by

p ( k ) = ( n k ) × p ( U R t = + 1 ) k × ( 1 p ( U R t = + 1 ) ) n k (3)

The random variable k is sometimes called a binomial variable. The probability to obtain k events or more (at least k events) in n trials is calculated as

p ( k X ) = p ( k = X ) + p ( k > X ) = k = X k = n ( ( n k ) × p ( U R t = + 1 ) k × ( 1 p ( U R t = + 1 ) ) n k ) (4)

The probability to obtain less than k events in n Bernoulli trials is calculated as

p ( k < X ) = 1 p ( k X ) = 1 k = X k = n ( ( n k ) × p ( U R t = + 1 ) k × ( 1 p ( U R t = + 1 ) ) n k ) (5)

2.3.2. Sufficient Condition (Conditio per Quam)

The formula of the conditio per quam [22] - [35] relationship was derived as

p ( EBV DNA Hodgkin slymphoma ) a + c + d N (6)

and used to proof the hypothesis: if presence of EBV infection (EBV DNA) then presence of Hodgkin’s lymphoma.

2.3.3. Necessary Condition (Conditio Sine Qua Non)

The formula of the conditio per quam [22] - [35] relationship was derived as

p ( EBV DNA Hodgkin slymphoma ) a + b + d N (7)

and used to proof the hypothesis: without presence of EBV infection (EBV DNA) no presence of Hodgkin’s lymphoma.

2.3.4. Necessary and Sufficient Condition

The necessary and sufficient condition relationship was defined [22] - [35] as

p ( EBV DNA Hodgkin slymphoma ) a + d N (8)

Scholium.

Historically, the notion sufficient condition is known since thousands of years. Many authors testified original contributions of the notion material implication only for Diodorus Cronus. Still, Philo the Logician (~300 BC), a member of a group of early Hellenistic philosophers (the Dialectical school), is the main forerunner of the notion material implication and has made some groundbreaking contributions [36] to the basics of this relationship. As it turns out, it is very hard to think of the “conditio per quam” relationship without considering the historical background of this concept. Remarkable as it is, Philo’s concept of the material implications came very close to that of modern concept material implication. In propositional logic, a conditional is generally symbolized as “p → q” or in spoken language “if p then q”. Both q and p are statements, with q the consequent and p the antecedent. Many times, the logical relation between the consequent and the antecedent is called a material implication. In general, a conditional “if p then q” is false only if p is true and q is false otherwise, in the three other possible combinations, the conditional is always true. In other words, to say that p is a sufficient condition for q is to say that the presence of p guarantees the presence of q. In particular, it is impossible to have p without q. If p is present, then q must be present too. To show that p is not sufficient for q, we come up with cases where p is present but q is not. It is well-known that the notion of a necessary condition can be used in defining what a sufficient condition is (and vice versa). In general, p is a necessary condition for q if it is impossible to have q without p. In fact, the absence of p guarantees the absence of q. Example (Condition: Our earth), without oxygen no fire. Table 5 may demonstrate this relationship.

In contrast to such a point of view, the opposite point of view is correct too. Thus far, there is a straightforward way to give a precise and comprehensive account of the meaning of the term necessary or sufficient condition itself. In other words, if fire is present then oxygen is present too. Table 6 may demonstrate this relationship.

Table 5. Without oxygen no fire (on our planet earth).

Table 6. If fire is present then oxygen is present too (on our planet earth).

Especially, necessary and sufficient conditions are converses of each other. Still, the fire is not the cause of oxygen and vice versa. Oxygen is note the cause of fire. In this example before, oxygen is a necessary condition, a conditio sine qua non, of fire. A necessary condition is sometimes also called “an essential condition” or a conditio sine qua non. In propositional logic, a necessary condition, a condition sine qua non, is generally symbolized as “p ← q” or in spoken language “without p no q”. Both q and p are statements, with p the antecedent and q the consequent. To show that p is not a necessary condition for q, it is necessary to find an event or circumstances where q is present (i.e. an illness) but p (i.e. a risk factor) is not. On any view, (classical) logic has as one of its goals to characterize the most basic, the most simple and the most general laws of objective reality. Especially, in classical logic, the notions of necessary conditions, of sufficient conditions of necessary and sufficient conditions et cetera are defined very precisely for a single event, for a single Bernoulli trial t. In point of fact, no matter how many times an experiment is repeated, the relationship of the conditio sine qua or of the conditio per quam which is defined for every single event will remain the same. Under conditions of independent trials this implies that no matter how many times an experiment is repeated, the probability of the conditio sine qua or of the conditio per quam of a single event at a single trial t remain the same which transfers the relationship of the conditio sine qua or of the conditio per quam et cetera into the sphere of (Bio-) statistics. Consequently, (Bio) statistics generalizes the notions of a sufficient or of a necessary condition from one single Bernoulli trial to N Bernoulli trials. However, in many practical applications, we may by confronted by circumstances which may be considered as approximately satisfying the notions of a sufficient or of a necessary condition. Thus far, under these circumstances, we will need to perform some tests to investigate, can we rely on our investigation.

2.3.5. The Central Limit Theorem

Many times, for some reason or other it is not possible to study exhaustively a whole population. Still, sometimes it is possible to draw a sample from such a population which itself can be studied in detail and used to convince us about the properties of the population. Roughly speaking, statistical inference derived from a randomly selected subset of a population (a sample) can lead to erroneous results. The question raised is how to deal with the uncertainty inherent in such results? The concept of confidence intervals, closely related to statistical significance testing, was formulated to provide an answer to this problem.

Confidence intervals, introduced to statistics by Jerzy Neyman in a paper published in 1937 [37] , specifies a range within a parameter, i.e. the population proportion π, with a certain probability, contain the desired parameter value. Most commonly, the 95% confidence interval is used. Interpreting a confidence interval involves a couple of important but subtle issues. In general, a 95% confidence interval for the value of a random number means that there is a 95% probability that the “true” value of the value of a random number is within the interval. Confidence intervals for proportions or a population mean of random variables which are not normally distributed in the population can be constructed while relying on the central limit theorem as long as the sample sizes and counts are big enough (i.e. a sample size of n = 30 and more). A formula, justified by the central limit theorem, is known as

p C r i t = p C a l c ± ( z Alpha / 2 × ( 1 N × p C a l c × ( 1 p C a l c ) 2 ) ) (9)

where pCalc is the sample proportion of successes in a Bernoulli trial process with N trials yielding X successes and N-X failures and z is i.e. the 1 − (Alpha/2) quantile of a standard normal distribution corresponding to the significance level alpha. For example, for a 95% confidence level alpha = 0.05 and z is z = 1.96. A very common technique for calculating binomial confidence intervals was published by Clopper-Pearson [38] . Agresti-Coull proposed another different method [39] for calculating binomial confidence intervals. A faster and an alternative way to determine the lower and upper “exact” confidence interval is justified by the F distribution [40] .

2.3.6. The Rule of Three

Furthermore, an approximate and conservative (one sided) confidence interval was developed by Louis [41] , Hanley et al. [42] and Jovanovic [43] known as the rule of three. Briefly sketched, the rule of three can be derived from the binomial model. Let πU denote the upper limit of the one-sided 100 × (1 − α)% confidence interval for the unknown proportion when in N independent trials no events occur [43] . Then πU is the value such that

π U = ( ln ( α ) n ) ( 3 n ) (10)

assuming that α = 0.05. In other words, an one-sided approximate upper 95% confidence bound for the true binomial population proportion π, the rate of occurrences in the population, based on a sample of size n where no successes are observed (p = 0) is 3/n [43] or given approximately by [0 < π < (3/n)]. The rule of three is a useful tool especially in the analysis of medical studies. Table 7 will illustrate this relationship.

Under conditions where a certain event did not occur [41] in a sample with n subjects (i.e. p = 0) the interval from 0 to (−ln(α)/n) is called a 100 × (1 − α)%

confidence interval for the binomial parameter for the rate of occurrences in the population.

Another special case of the binomial distribution is based on a sample of size n where only successes are observed (p = 1). Accordingly, the lower limit of a one-sided 100 × (1 − α)% confidence interval for a binomial probability πL, the rate of occurrences in the population, based on a sample of size n where only successes are observed is given approximately by [(1− (−ln(α)/n)) < π < +1] or (assuming α = 0.05)

π L = 1 ( ln ( α ) n ) 1 ( 3 n ) (11)

Table 8 may illustrate this relationship.

To construct a two-sided 100 × (1 − (α))% interval according to the rule of three, it is necessary to take a one-sided 100 × (1 − (α/2))% confidence interval. In this study, we will use the rule of three [44] too, to calculate the confidence interval for the value of a random number.

Table 7. The one-sided approximate upper 100 × (1 − α)% confidence bound where no successes (p = 0) are observed.

Table 8. The one-sided approximate upper 100 × (1 − α)% confidence bound where only successes are observed.

2.3.7. Fisher’s Exact Test

A test statistics of independent and more or less normally distributed data which follow a chi-squared distribution is valid as with many statistical tests due to the central limit theorem. Especially, with large samples, a chi-squared distribution can be used. A sample is considered as large when the sample size n is n = 30 or more. With a small sample (n < 30), the central limit theorem does not apply and erroneous results could potentially be obtained from the few observations if the same is applied. Thus far, when the number of observations obtained from a population is too small, a more appropriate test for of analysis of categorical data i.e. contingency tables is R. A. Fisher’s exact test [45] . Fisher’s exact test is valid for all sample sizes and calculates the significance of the p-value (i.e. the deviation from a null hypothesis) exactly even if in practice it is employed when sample size is small. Fisher’s exact test is called exact because the same uses the exact hypergeometric distribution to compute the p-value rather than the approximate chi-square distribution. Still, computations involved in Fisher’s exact test can be time consuming to calculate by hand.

2.3.8. Hypergeometric Distribution

The hypergeometric distribution, illustrated in a table (Table 9), is a discrete probability distribution which describes the probability of a events/successes in a sample with the size 0Wt, without replacement, from a finite population of the size N which contains exactly RUt objects with a certain feature while each event is either a success or a failure. The formula for the hypergeometric distribution, a discrete probability distribution, is

p ( a ) = ( U R t a ) × ( N U R t W 0 t a ) ( N W 0 t ) (12)

The hypergeometric distribution has a wide range of applications. The Hypergeometric distribution can be approximated by a Binomial distribution. The elements of the population being sampled are classified into one of two mutually exclusive categories: either conditio sine qua non or no conditio sine qua non relationship. We are sampling without replacement from a finite population. How probable is it to draw specific c events/successes out of 0Wt total draws from an aforementioned population of the size N? The hypergeometric distribution, as shown in a table (Table 10) is of use to calculate how probable is it to obtain c = (0Wt − a) events out of N events.

Table 9. The hypergeometric distribution.

Table 10. The hypergeometric distribution and conditio sine qua non.

2.3.9. Statistical Hypothesis Testing

A statistical hypothesis test is a method to extract some inferences from data. A hypothesis is compared as an alternative hypothesis. Under which conditions does the outcomes of a study lead to a rejection of the null hypothesis for a pre-specified level of significance. According to the rules of a proof by contradiction, a null hypothesis (H0) is a statement which one seeks to disproof. The related specific alternative hypothesis (HA) is opposed to the null hypothesis such that if null hypothesis (H0) is true, the alternative hypothesis (HA) is false and vice versa. If the alternative hypothesis (HA) is true then the null hypothesis (H0) is false. In principle, a null hypothesis that is true can be rejected (type I error) which lead us to falsely infer the existence of something which is not given. The significance level, also denoted as α (alpha) is the probability of rejecting a null hypothesis when the same is true. A type II error is given, if we falsely infer the absence of something which in reality is given. A null hypothesis can be false but a statistical test may fail to reject such a false null hypothesis. The probability of accepting a null hypothesis when the same is false (type II error), is denoted by the Greek letter β (beta) and related to the power of a test (which equals 1 − β). The power of a test indicates the probability by which the test correctly rejects the null hypothesis (H0) when a specific alternative hypothesis (HA) is true. Most investigator assess the power of a tests using 1 − β = 0.80 as a standard for adequacy. A tabularized relation between truth/falseness of the null hypothesis and outcomes of the test are shown precisely within a table (Table 11).

In general, it is 1 − α + α = 1 or (1 − α − β) + α = 1− β. Figure 1 may illustrate these relationships.

2.3.10. The Mathematical Formula of the Causal Relationship k

The mathematical formula of the causal relationship k [22] - [35] defined as

k ( U R t , W 0 t ) ( ( N × a ) ( U R t × W 0 t ) ) ( U R t × U _ R t ) × ( W 0 × W _ 0 t ) 2 (13)

and the chi-square distribution [46] were applied to determine the significance of causal relationship between a EBV and HL. A one-tailed test makes it much easier to reject a null hypothesis (no causal relationship) while a two-tailed test makes it more difficult to reject a null hypothesis and is more conservative on this account. For this reason, in causal relationship testing, a two-tailed test is preferred. In general, a p value of less than 0.05 is considered as significant. In this context, what is the necessary connection between a cause and effect? What

Figure 1. The relationship between error types.

Table 11. Table of error types.

ties a cause and its own effect together? Is there a necessary connection between a cause and effect at all? Theoretically, it is neither justified nor necessary to reduce causation as such to an act of observation or measurement. Sill, case-control studies, experiments, observations et cetera can help us to recognize cause effect relationships. In this context it is necessary to stress out that every single event (effect) has its own cause, which is the logical foundation of the mathematical formula of the causal relationship k. It is therefore entirely clear that this is the fundamental difference to Pearson’s methodological approach. Obviously, although under some certain specified circumstances Pearson’s product-moment correlation coefficient [47] or Pearson’s Phi [48] coefficient can yield the same numerical result as the mathematical formula of the causal relationship k, there is nothing truly exciting about such a coincidence. Nevertheless, when conducting experiments and analyzing data, views in which correlation and causation are brought very close together are incorrect and worthless. The mathematical formula of the causal relationship k is neither identical nor can the same mathematical formula be reduced to Pearson’s product-moment correlation coefficient [47] or to Pearson’s Phi [48] Coefficient (Mean Square Contingency Coefficient). In contrast to Pearson’s product-moment correlation coefficient and to Pearson’s Phi Coefficient (Mean Square Contingency Coefficient) the mathematical formula of the causal relationship k is defined and valid at every single Bernoulli trial t or at every single event. Sir Austin Bradford Hill (1897-1991), an English epidemiologist, proposed 1965 a set of nine criteria (Strength, Consistency, Specificity, Temporality, Biological gradient, Plausibility, Coherence, Experiment, Analogy) [49] to establish epidemiologic evidence of a causal relationship (Bradford Hill criteria). In point of fact, Bredford’s “fourth characteristic is the temporal relationship of the association” [49] and in last consequence the “post hoc ergo propter hoc” logical fallacy. Causation cannot be derived from the “post hoc ergo propter hoc” [35] logical fallacy. Consequently, the Mathematical Formula of the causal relationship k can neither be reduced to the Bradford Hill criteria nor is the same just a mathematization of Bradford Hill criteria.

2.3.11. The Chi Square Distribution

The chi-squared distribution [46] is a widely known distribution and used in hypothesis testing, in inferential statistics or in construction of confidence intervals. The critical values of the chi square distribution are visualized by Table 12.

2.3.12. The X2 Goodness of Fit Test

A chi-square goodness of fit test can be applied to determine whether sample data are consistent with a hypothesized distribution. The chi-square goodness of fit test is appropriate when some conditions are met. A view of these conditions are simple random sampling, categorical variables and an expected value of the number of sample observations which is at least 5. The null hypothesis (H0) and its own alternative hypothesis (HA) are stated in such a way that they are mutually exclusive. In point of fact, if the null hypothesis (H0) is true, the other, alternative hypothesis (HA), must be false; and vice versa. For a chi-square goodness of fit test, the hypotheses can take the following form.

Table 12. The critical values of the chi square distribution (degrees of freedom: 1).

H0: The sample distribution agrees with the hypothetical (theoretical) distribution.

HA: The sample distribution does not agree with the hypothetical (theoretical) distribution.

The X2 Goodness-of-Fit Test can be shown schematically as

χ 2 t = + 1 t = + N ( ( Observed t Expected t ) 2 Expected t ) (14)

The degrees of freedom are calculated as N − 1. If there is no discrepancy between an observed and a theoretical distribution, then X2 = 0. As the discrepancy between an observed and a theoretical distribution becomes larger, the X2 becomes larger. This X2 values are evaluated by the known X2 distribution.

The original X2 values are calculated from an original theoretical distribution, which is continuous, whereas the approximation by the X2 Goodness of fit test we are using is discrete. Thus far, there is a tendency to underestimate the probability, which means that the number of rejections of the null hypothesis can increase too much and must be corrected downward. Such an adjustment (Yate’s correction for continuity) is used only when there is one degree of freedom. When there is more than one degree of freedom, the same adjustment is not used. Applying this to the formula above, we find the X2 Goodness-of-Fit Test with continuity correction shown schematically as

χ 2 t = + 1 t = + N ( ( | Observed t Expected t | ( 1 2 ) ) 2 Expected t ) (15)

When the term (|Observedt − Expectedt|) is less than 1/2, the continuity correction should be omitted.

1) The X² Goodness of Fit Test of a Sufficient Condition

The theoretical (hypothetical) distribution of a sufficient condition is shown schematically by the 2 × 2 table (Table 13).

The theoretical distribution of a sufficient condition (conditio pre quam) is determined by the fact that b = 0. The X2 Goodness-of-Fit Test with continuity correction of a sufficient condition (conditio per quam) is calculated as

Table 13. The theoretical distribution of a sufficient condition (conditio pre quam).

χ 2 ( IMP ) ( ( | a ( a + b ) | ( 1 2 ) ) 2 ( a + b ) ) + ( ( | ( c + d ) ( c + d ) | ( 1 2 ) ) 2 ( c + d ) ) = ( ( | a ( a + b ) | ( 1 2 ) ) 2 ( a + b ) ) + 0 (16)

or more simplified as

χ 2 ( IMP ) ( ( | b | ( 1 2 ) ) 2 ( a + b ) ) + 0 (17)

Under these circumstances, the degree of freedom is d.f. = N 1 = 2 1 = 1 .

2) The X2 goodness of fit test of a necessary condition

The theoretical (hypothetical) distribution of a necessary condition is shown schematically by the 2 × 2 table (Table 14).

The theoretical distribution of a necessary condition (conditio sine qua non) is determined by the fact that c = 0. The X2 Goodness-of-Fit Test with continuity correction of a necessary condition (conditio sine qua non) is calculated as

χ 2 ( SINE ) ( ( | ( a + b ) ( a + b ) | ( 1 2 ) ) 2 ( a + b ) ) + ( ( | ( d ) ( c + d ) | ( 1 2 ) ) 2 ( c + d ) ) = 0 + ( ( | d ( c + d ) | ( 1 2 ) ) 2 ( c + d ) ) (18)

or more simplified as

χ 2 ( SINE ) ( ( | c | ( 1 2 ) ) 2 ( c + d ) ) + 0 (19)

Table 14. The theoretical distribution of a necessary condition (conditio sine qua non).

Under these circumstances, the degree of freedom is d.f. = N 1 = 2 1 = 1 .

3) The X2 goodness of fit test of a necessary and sufficient condition

The theoretical (hypothetical) distribution of a necessary and sufficient condition is shown schematically by the 2 × 2 table (Table 15).

The theoretical distribution of a necessary and sufficient condition is determined by the fact that b = 0 and that c = 0. The X2 Goodness-of-Fit Test with continuity correction of a necessary and sufficient condition is calculated as

χ 2 ( NecessaryANDSufficient ) ( ( | ( a ) ( a + b ) | ( 1 2 ) ) 2 ( a + b ) ) + ( ( | ( d ) ( c + d ) | ( 1 2 ) ) 2 ( c + d ) ) (20)

or more simplified as

χ 2 ( NecessaryANDSufficient ) ( ( | b | ( 1 2 ) ) 2 ( a + b ) ) + ( ( | c | ( 1 2 ) ) 2 ( c + d ) ) (21)

Under these circumstances, the degree of freedom is d.f. = N 1 = 2 1 = 1 .

3. Results

3.1. Epstein-Bar Virus Is a Conditio sine qua Non of Hodgkin’s Lymphoma

Claims.

Null hypothesis:

An infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus is a conditio sine qua non of Hodgkin’s lymphoma.

Alternative hypothesis:

An infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus is not a conditio sine qua non of Hodgkin’s lymphoma.

Significance level (Alpha) below which the null hypothesis will be rejected: 0.05.

Proof.

The data of an infection by Epstein-Bar virus and Hodgkin’s lymphoma are viewed in the 2 × 2 table (Table 1). The X2 Goodness-of-Fit Test with continuity

Table 15. The theoretical distribution of a necessary and sufficient condition.

correction of a necessary condition (conditio sine qua non) known to be defined as p (Epstein-Bar virus DNA ← Hodgkin’s lymphoma) is calculated as

χ 2 ( SINE ) ( ( | c | ( 1 2 ) ) 2 ( c + d ) ) + 0 = ( ( | 9 | ( 1 2 ) ) 2 ( 9 + 25 ) ) = 2.125

Under these circumstances, the degree of freedom is d.f. = N 1 = 2 1 = 1 . The critical X2 (significance level alpha = 0.05) is known to be 3.841458821 (Table 12). The calculated X2 value = 2.125 and less than the critical X2 = 3.841458821. Hence, our calculated X2 value = 2.125 is not significant and we accept our null hypothesis. Due to this evidence, we do not reject the null hypothesis in favor of the alternative hypotheses. In other words, the sample distribution agrees with the hypothetical (theoretical) distribution. Our hypothetical distribution was the distribution of the necessary condition. Thus far, the data as published by Dinand et al. [17] do support our null hypothesis that an infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus is a conditio sine qua non of Hodgkin’s lymphoma. In other words, without an infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus no Hodgkin’s lymphoma.

Q.e.d.

3.2. Epstein-Bar Virus Is a Conditio per quam of Hodgkin’s Lymphoma

Claims.

Null hypothesis:

An infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus is a conditio per quam of Hodgkin’s lymphoma.

(p0 > pCrit).

Alternative hypothesis:

An infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus is not a conditio per quam of Hodgkin’s lymphoma.

(p0 < pCrit).

Significance level (Alpha) below which the null hypothesis will be rejected: 0.05.

Proof.

The data of an infection by Epstein-Bar virus and Hodgkin’s lymphoma are viewed in the 2 × 2 table (Table 1). The proportion of successes in the sample of a conditio per quam relationship p (Epstein-Bar virus DNA → Hodgkin’s lymphoma) is calculated [22] - [35] as

p ( EBVDNA Hodgkin slymphoma ) = ( 126 + 9 + 25 ) 160 = 160 160 = 1

The critical value pCrit (significance level alpha = 0.05) is calculated [39] - [44] as

p C r i t = 1 3 160 = 0 .981276673

The critical value is pCrit = 0.981276673 and is less than the proportion of successes calculated as p (Epstein-Bar virus DNA → Hodgkin’s lymphoma) = 1. Due to this evidence, we do not reject the null hypothesis in favor of the alternative hypotheses. The data as published by Dinand et al. [17] do support our Null hypothesis that an infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus is a conditio per quam of Hodgkin’s lymphoma. In other words, if an infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus is present then Hodgkin’s lymphoma is present too.

Q.e.d.

3.3. Epstein-Bar Virus Is the Cause of Hodgkin’s Lymphoma

Claims.

Null hypothesis: (no causal relationship)

There is no causal relationship between an infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus and Hodgkin’s lymphoma.

Alternative hypothesis: (causal relationship)

There is a causal relationship between an infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus and Hodgkin’s lymphoma.

(k <> 0).

Conditions.

Alpha level = 5%.

The two tailed critical Chi square value (degrees of freedom = 1) for alpha level 5% is 3.841458821.

Proof.

The data for this hypothesis test are illustrated in the 2 × 2 table (Table 1). The causal relationship k (EBV DNA, Hodgkin’s lymphoma) is calculated [22] - [35] as

k ( EBV DNA,Hodgkin slymphoma ) = ( ( 160 × 126 ) ( 126 × 135 ) ) ( 126 × 34 ) × ( 135 × 25 ) 2 = + 0 .82841687

The value of the test statistic k = +0.82841687 is equivalent to a calculated [22] - [35] chi-square value of

χ Calculated 2 = 160 × ( ( ( 160 × 126 ) ( 126 × 135 ) ) ( 126 × 34 ) × ( 135 × 25 ) 2 ) × ( ( ( 160 × 126 ) ( 126 × 135 ) ) ( 126 × 34 ) × ( 135 × 25 ) 2 ) χ Calculated 2 = 160 × 0 .82841687 × 0 .82841687 χ Calculated 2 = 109 .8039216

The chi-square statistic, uncorrected for continuity, is calculated as X2 = 109.8039216 and thus far equivalent to a P value of 0.000000000000000000000000108179. The calculated chi-square statistic exceeds the critical chi-square value of 3.841458821 (Table 12). Consequently, we reject the null hypothesis and accept the alternative hypotheses. There is a highly significant causal relationship between an infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus and Hodgkin’s lymphoma (k = +0.82841687, p Value = 0.000000000000000000000000108179). The result is significant at p < 0.001.

Q.e.d.

3.4. Epstein-Bar Virus Is a Conditio sine qua Non of Hodgkin’s Lymphoma

Claims.

Null hypothesis:

An infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus is a conditio sine qua non of Hodgkin’s lymphoma.

Alternative hypothesis:

An infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus is not a conditio sine qua non of Hodgkin’s lymphoma.

Significance level (Alpha) below which the null hypothesis will be rejected: 0.05.

Proof.

The data of an infection by Epstein-Bar virus and Hodgkin’s lymphoma are viewed in the 2 × 2 table (Table 2). The X2 Goodness-of-Fit Test with continuity correction of a necessary condition (conditio sine qua non) known to be defined as p (Epstein-Bar virus DNA ← Hodgkin’s lymphoma) [22] - [35] is calculated as

χ 2 ( SINE ) ( ( | c | ( 1 2 ) ) 2 ( c + d ) ) + 0 = ( ( | 11 | ( 1 2 ) ) 2 ( 11 + 70 ) ) = 1 .361111111 (22)

Under these circumstances, the degree of freedom is d.f. = N 1 = 2 1 = 1 . The critical X2 (significance level alpha = 0.05) is known to be 3.841458821 (Table 12). The calculated X2 value is 1.361111111and is less than the critical X2 = 3.841458821. Hence, our calculated X2 value is 1.361111111 and is not significant and we accept the null hypothesis. Due to this evidence, we do not reject the null hypothesis in favor of the alternative hypotheses. In other words, the sample distribution agrees with the hypothetical (theoretical) distribution. Our hypothetical distribution was the distribution of the necessary condition. Thus far, the data as published by Dinand et al. [21] do support our null hypothesis that an infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus is a conditio sine qua non of Hodgkin’s lymphoma. In other words, without an infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus no Hodgkin’s lymphoma.

Q.e.d.

3.5. An Infection of Human Lymph Nodes by Epstein-Bar Virus Is a Conditio per quam of Hodgkin’s Lymphoma

Claims.

Null hypothesis:

An infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus is a conditio per quam of Hodgkin’s lymphoma.

(p0 > pCrit).

Alternative hypothesis:

An infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus is not a conditio per quam of Hodgkin’s lymphoma.

(p0 < pCrit).

Significance level (Alpha) below which the null hypothesis will be rejected: 0.05.

Proof.

The data of an infection by Epstein-Bar virus and Hodgkin’s lymphoma are viewed in the 2 × 2 table (Table 2). The proportion of successes in the sample of a conditio per quam relationship p(Epstein-Bar virus DNA → Hodgkin’s lymphoma) is calculated [22] - [35] as

p ( EBV DNA Hodgkin slymphoma ) = ( 19 + 11 + 70 ) 100 = 100 100 = 1

The critical value pCrit (significance level alpha = 0.05) is calculated [39] - [44] as

p C r i t = 1 3 100 = 0 .97

The critical value is pCrit = 0.97 and is less than the proportion of successes calculated as p(Epstein-Bar virus DNA → Hodgkin’s lymphoma) = 1. Due to this evidence, we do not reject the null hypothesis in favor of the alternative hypotheses. The data as published by Dinand et al. [21] do support our Null hypothesis that an infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus is a conditio per quam of Hodgkin’s lymphoma. In other words, if an infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus then Hodgkin’s lymphoma.

Q.e.d.

3.6. Epstein-Bar Virus Is the Cause of Hodgkin’s Lymphoma

Claims.

Null hypothesis: (no causal relationship)

There is no causal relationship between an infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus and Hodgkin’s lymphoma.

Alternative hypothesis: (causal relationship)

There is a causal relationship between an infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus and Hodgkin’s lymphoma.

(k<>0).

Conditions.

Alpha level = 5%.

The two tailed critical Chi square value (degrees of freedom = 1) for alpha level 5% is 3.841458821.

Proof.

The data for this hypothesis test are illustrated in the 2 × 2 table (Table 2). The causal relationship k (EBV DNA, Hodgkin’s lymphoma) is calculated [22] - [35] as

k ( EBV DNA,Hodgkin slymphoma ) = ( ( 100 × 19 ) ( 30 × 19 ) ) ( 30 × 70 ) × ( 19 × 81 ) 2 = + 0 .739814235

The value of the test statistic k = +0.739814235 is equivalent to a calculated [22] - [35] chi-square value of

χ Calculated 2 = 100 × ( ( 100 × 19 ) ( 30 × 19 ) ) ( 30 × 70 ) × ( 19 × 81 ) 2 × ( ( 100 × 19 ) ( 30 × 19 ) ) ( 30 × 70 ) × ( 19 × 81 ) 2 χ Calculated 2 = 100 × 0 .739814235 × 0 .739814235 χ Calculated 2 = 54 .7325102881

The chi-square statistic, uncorrected for continuity, is calculated as X2 = 54.7325102881 and thus far equivalent to a P value of 0.000000000000138. The calculated chi-square statistic exceeds the critical chi-square value of 3.841458821 (Table 12). Consequently, we reject the null hypothesis and accept the alternative hypotheses. There is a highly significant causal relationship between an infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus and Hodgkin’s lymphoma (k = +0.739814235, p Value = 0.000000000000138). The result is significant at p < 0.001.

Q.e.d.

4. Discussion

A case-control study or a retrospective study is a type of an observational study where investigators compare a set of people with a certain disease (the cases) and a set of people with all but this certain disease (the controls) with regard to a special condition, cause or factor. Case-control studies usually require a smaller sample sizes than equivalent cohort studies and are cheap and quick. As a consequence, many factors, conditions or causes can be studied simultaneously. Still, etiological questions are ideally studied not through the case-control approach. A cohort study is a better type of an observational study to investigate etiological hypothesis, especially when a study population, which is free of a disease, is used at the outset. By contrast to a case-control study, in a cohort study, it is investigated whether a disease develops or not. In particular, a case-control study may provide data which are inaccurate under certain circumstances and is very likely to suffer from bias error. Among many source of bias, the problems arise especially from the way how controls are sampled with the consequence that the data as collected in a case-control study may not be appropriate to perform some causal investigations of interest. To be persuasive, case-control studies need to be conducted very carefully. Further details about case control studies are given by secondary literature [50] . Despite of the view disadvantages of case-control studies discussed above, Dinand et al. [17] [21] detected EBV DNA by in situ hybridization (ISH), which cannot be ignored. The in situ hybridization, like any method, is not completely free of bias and is labeled with some severe limitations. Still, the in situ hybridization provides the opportunity to distinguish EBV DNA in tumor cells from EBV DNA in non-tumor cells. In general, it is known that a great proportion of HL tissues is able to harbor EBV within tumor cells. Emerging evidence suggests that EBV is causality related to Hodgkin’s lymphoma. According to the data as published by Dinand et al. [17] , without an infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus no Hodgkin’s lymphoma. In the same context, there is a highly significant causal relationship between an infection of human lymph nodes by Epstein-Bar virus and Hodgkin’s lymphoma (k = +0.82841687, p-value = 0.000000000000000000000000108179). Thus far, Epstein-Bar virus is not only a cause, but the cause of Hodgkin’s lymphoma. The challenge is to unravel this complexity of the relationship between Epstein Bar virus and Hodgkin’s lymphoma by detailed consideration of the function of EBV genes in the appropriate (tumor) cellular context. The hope is justified that this approach has revealed the most fundamental aspects of HL pathogenesis and that the same has paved the way for a more targeted and individual therapies for HL patients. Even if EBV is the cause of HL, many times a specific therapy is not indicated for most patients with an EBV infection. In point of fact, some drugs, i. e. acyclovir, are able to inhibit EBV replication and to reduce viral shedding. Sometimes, corticosteroid therapy is considered for patients with severe complications of an EBV infection and is able to shorten the duration of some symptoms and fever associated with an EBV infection. In point of fact, vaccination against EBV might be useful especially for people who are seronegative for EBV. In this context, preliminary studies in which EBV-seronegative children were vaccinated with vaccinia virus expressing gp350 where to some extent effective [51] [52] .

5. Conclusion

Epstein-Bar virus is the cause of Hodgkin’s lymphoma (k = +0.82841687, p Value = 0.000000000000000000000000108179).

Acknowledgements

The public domain software GnuPlot was used to draw the figure.

Cite this paper

Barukčić, I (2018) Epstein Bar Virus―The Cause of Hodgkin’s Lymphoma. Journal of Biosciences and Medicines, 6, 75-100. https://doi.org/10.4236/jbm.2018.61008

References

  1. 1. Epstein, M.A., Achong, B.G. and Barr, Y.M. (1964) Virus Particles in Cultured Lymphoblasts from Burkitt’s Lymphoma. Lancet, 283, 702-703. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(64)91524-7

  2. 2. Cohen, J.I. (2000) Epstein-Barr Virus Infection. The New England Journal of Medicine, 343, 481-492. https://doi.org/10.1056/NEJM200008173430707

  3. 3. Meij, P., Vervoort, M.B., Aarbiou, J., van Dissel, P., Brink, A., Bloemena, E., Meijer, C.J. and Middeldorp, J. (1999) Restricted Low-Level Human Antibody Responses against Epstein—Barr Virus (EBV)—Encoded Latent Membrane Protein 1 in a Subgroup of Patients with EBV-Associated Diseases. The Journal of Infectious Diseases, 179, 1108-1115. https://doi.org/10.1086/314704

  4. 4. zur Hausen, H., Schulte-Holthausen, H., Klein, G., Henle, W., Henle, G., Clifford, P. and Santesson, L. (1970) EBV DNA in Biopsies of Burkitt Tumours and Anaplastic Carcinomas of the Nasopharynx. Nature, 228, 1056-1058. https://doi.org/10.1038/2281056a0

  5. 5. Golden, R.L. (1968) Infectious Mononucleosis with Epstein-Barr Virus Antibodies in Older Ages. JAMA: The Journal of the American Medical Association, 205, 595. https://doi.org/10.1001/jama.1968.03140340065021

  6. 6. Kapatai, G. and Murray, P. (2007) Contribution of the Epstein-Barr Virus to the Molecular Pathogenesis of Hodgkin Lymphoma. Journal of Clinical Pathology, 60, 1342-1349. https://doi.org/10.1136/jcp.2007.050146

  7. 7. Hodgkin, T. (1832) On Some Morbid Experiences of the Absorbent Glands and Spleen. Medico-Chirurgical Transactions, 17, 69-97. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2116706/

  8. 8. Harris, N.L., Jaffe, E.S., Stein, H., Banks, P.M., Chan, J.K., Cleary, M.L., Delsol, G., De Wolf-Peeters, C., Falini, B., Gatter, K.C., et al. (1994) A Revised European-American Classification of Lymphoid Neoplasms: A Proposal from the International Lymphoma Study Group. Blood, 84, 1361-1392. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/8068936

  9. 9. Sternberg, C. (1898) über Eine Eigenartige Unter Dem Bilde Der Pseudoleukamie Verlaufende Tuberculose Des Lymphatischen Apparates. Zeitschrift für Heilkunde, 19, 21-90.

  10. 10. Reed, D. (1902) On the Pathological Changes in Hodgkin’s Disease, with Special Reference to Its Relation to Tuberculosis. The Johns Hopkins Hospital Reports, 10, 133-196.

  11. 11. Küppers, R., Rajewsky, K., Zhao, M., Simons, G., Laumann, R., Fischer, R. and Hansmann, M.L. (1994) Hodgkin Disease: Hodgkin and Reed-Sternberg Cells Picked from Histological Sections Show Clonal Immunoglobulin Gene Rearrangements and Appear to Be Derived from B Cells at Various Stages of Development. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 91, 10962-10966. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.91.23.10962

  12. 12. Newell, G.R. and Rawlings, W. (1972) Evidence for Environmental Factors in the Etiology of Hodgkin’s Disease. Journal of Chronic Diseases, 25, 261-267. https://doi.org/10.1016/0021-9681(72)90162-2

  13. 13. Goldman, J.M. and Aisenberg, A.C. (1970) Incidence of Antibody to EB Virus, Herpes Simplex, and Cytomegalovirus in Hodgkin’s Disease. Cancer, 26, 327-331. https://doi.org/10.1002/1097-0142(197008)26:2<327::AID-CNCR2820260213>3.0.CO;2-8

  14. 14. Levine, P.H. (1970) E.B. Virus and Lymphomas. Lancet, 296, 771. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(70)90243-6

  15. 15. Levine, P.H., Ablashi, D.V., Berard, C.W., et al. (1971) Elevated Antibody Titers to Epstein-Barr Virus in Hodgkin’s Disease. Cancer, 27, 416-421. https://doi.org/10.1002/1097-0142(197102)27:2<416::AID-CNCR2820270227>3.0.CO;2-W

  16. 16. Weiss, L.M., Strickler, J.G., Warnke, R.A., Purtilo, D.T. and Sklar, J. (1987) Epstein-Barr Viral DNA in Tissues of Hodgkin’s Disease. American Journal of Pathology, 129, 86-91. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC1899692/

  17. 17. Dinand, V., Dawar, R., Arya, L.S., Unni, R., Mohanty, B. and Singh, R. (2007) Hodgkin’s Lymphoma in Indian Children: Prevalence and Significance of Epstein-Barr Virus Detection in Hodgkin’s and Reed-Sternberg Cells. European Journal of Cancer, 43, 161-168. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ejca.2006.08.036

  18. 18. Chae, Y.K., Arya, A., Chiec, L., Shah, H., Rosenberg, A., Patel, S., Raparia, K., Choi, J., Wainwright, D.A., Villaflor, V., Cristofanilli, M. and Giles, F. (2017) Challenges and Future of Biomarker Tests in the Era of Precision Oncology: Can We Rely on Immunohistochemistry (IHC) or Fluorescence In Situ Hybridization (FISH) to Select the Optimal Patients for Matched Therapy? Oncotarget, 8, 100863-100898. https://doi.org/10.18632/oncotarget.19809

  19. 19. Coons, A.H., Creech, H.J. and Jones, R.N. (1941) Immunological Properties of an Antibody Containing a Fluorescent Group. Experimental Biology and Medicine, 47, 200-202. https://doi.org/10.3181/00379727-47-13084p

  20. 20. Gall, J.G. and Pardue, M.L. (1969) Formation and Detection of RNA-DNA Hybrid Molecules in Cytological Preparations. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 63, 378-383. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.63.2.378

  21. 21. Dinand, V., Sachdeva, A., Datta, S., Bhalla, S., Kalra, M., Wattal, C. and Radhakrishnan, N. (2015) Plasma Epstein Barr Virus (EBV) DNA as a biomarker for EBV-Associated Hodgkin Lymphoma. Indian Pediatrics, 52, 681-685. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13312-015-0696-9

  22. 22. Barukcic, I. (1989) Die Kausalitat. Wissenschaftsverlag, Hamburg, 218.

  23. 23. Barukcic, I. (1997) Die Kausalitat. Scientia, Wilhelmshaven, 374.

  24. 24. Barukcic, I. (2005) Causality. New Statistical Methods. Books on Demand, Norderstedt, 488.

  25. 25. Barukcic, I. (2006) Causality. New Statistical Methods. Second English Edition, Books on Demand, Norderstedt, 488.

  26. 26. Barukcic, I. (2006) New Method for Calculating Causal Relationships. Proceeding of XXIIIrd International Biometric Conference, McGill University, Montréal, 16-21 July 2006, 49.

  27. 27. Barukcic, I. (2011) Causality I. A Theory of Energy, Time and Space. Lulu, Morrisville, NC, 648.

  28. 28. Barukcic, I. (2011) Causality II. A Theory of Energy, Time and Space. Lulu, Morrisville, NC, 376.

  29. 29. Barukcic, I. (2012) The Deterministic Relationship between Cause and Effect. International Biometric Conference, Kobe, Japan, 26-31 August 2012. https://www.biometricsociety.org/conference-abstracts/2012/programme/p1-5/P-1/249-P-1-30.pdf

  30. 30. Barukcic, I. (2016) The Mathematical Formula of the Causal Relationship k. International Journal of Applied Physics and Mathematics, 6, 45-65. https://doi.org/10.17706/ijapm.2016.6.2.45-65

  31. 31. Barukcic, K. and Barukcic, I. (2016) Epstein Barr Virus—The Cause of Multiple Sclerosis. Journal of Applied Mathematics and Physics, 4, 1042-1053. https://doi.org/10.4236/jamp.2016.46109

  32. 32. Barukcic, I. (2016) Unified Field Theory. Journal of Applied Mathematics and Physics, 4, 1379-1438. https://doi.org/10.4236/jamp.2016.48147

  33. 33. Barukcic, I. (2017) Helicobacter pylori—The Cause of Human Gastric Cancer. Journal of Biosciences and Medicines, 5, 1-19. https://doi.org/10.4236/jbm.2017.52001

  34. 34. Barukcic, I. (2017) Anti Bohr—Quantum Theory and Causality. International Journal of Applied Physics and Mathematics, 7, 93-111. https://doi.org/10.17706/ijapm.2017.7.2.93-111

  35. 35. Barukcic, I. (2017) Theoriae Causalitatis Principia Mathematica. Books on Demand, Norderstedt, 244. https://www.bod.de/buchshop/theoriae-causalitatis-principia-mathematica-ilija-barukcic-9783744815932

  36. 36. Astorga, M.L. (2015) Diodorus Cronus and Philo of Megara: Two Accounts of the Conditional. Rupkatha Journal on Interdisciplinary Studies in Humanities, 7, 9-16.

  37. 37. Neyman, J. (1937) Outline of a Theory of Statistical Estimation Based on the Classical Theory of Probability. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A, 236, 333-380. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsta.1937.0005

  38. 38. Clopper, C. and Pearson, E.S. (1934) The Use of Confidence or Fiducial Limits Illustrated in the Case of the Binomial. Biometrika, 26, 404-413. https://doi.org/10.1093/biomet/26.4.404

  39. 39. Agresti, A. and Coull, B.A. (1998) Approximate Is Better than “Exact” for Interval Estimation of Binomial Proportions. The American Statistician, 52, 119-126. https://doi.org/10.2307/2685469

  40. 40. Leemis, L.M. and Trivedi, K.S. (1996) A Comparison of Approximate Interval Estimators for the Bernoulli Parameter. The American Statistician, 50, 63-68. https://doi.org/10.2307/2685046

  41. 41. Louis, T.A. (1981) Confidence Intervals for a Binomial Parameter after Observing No Successes. The American Statistician, 35, 154. https://doi.org/10.1080/00031305.1981.10479337

  42. 42. Hanley, J.A. and Lippman-Hand, A. (1983) If Nothing Goes Wrong, Is Everything All Right? JAMA: The Journal of the American Medical Association, 249, 1743-1745. https://doi.org/10.1001/jama.1983.03330370053031

  43. 43. Jovanovic, B.D. and Levy, P.S. (1997) A Look at the Rule of Three. The American Statistician, 51, 137-139. https://doi.org/10.1080/00031305.1997.10473947

  44. 44. Rumke, C.L. (1975) Implications of the Statement: No Side Effects Were Observed. The New England Journal of Medicine, 292, 372-373. https://doi.org/10.1056/NEJM197502132920723

  45. 45. Fisher, R.A. (1922) On the Interpretation of X2 from Contingency Tables, and the Calculation of P. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, 85, 87-94. https://doi.org/10.2307/2340521

  46. 46. Pearson, K. (1900) On the Criterion That a Given System of Deviations from the Probable in the Case of a Correlated System of Variables Is Such That It Can Be Reasonably Supposed to Have Arisen from Random Sampling. Philosophical Magazine Series, 5, 157-175. https://doi.org/10.1080/14786440009463897

  47. 47. Pearson, K. (1896) VII. Mathematical Contributions to the Theory of Evolution—III. Regression, Heredity, and Panmixia. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London Series A, 187, 253-218. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsta.1896.0007

  48. 48. Pearson, K. (1904) Mathematical Contributions to the Theory of Evolution—XIII. On the Theory of Contingency and Its Relation to Association and Normal Correlation. Dulau and Co., London, 1-35. https://archive.org/details/cu31924003064833

  49. 49. Hill, A.B. (1965) The Environment and Disease: Association or Causation? Proceedings of the Royal Society of Medicine, 58, 295-300. https://doi.org/10.1177/0141076814562718

  50. 50. Woodward, M. (2014) Epidemiology: Study Design and Data Analysis. Third Edition, Taylor & Francis Group, LLC, Boca Raton, 819.

  51. 51. Martin-Subero, J.I., Gesk, S., Harder, L., et al. (2002) Recurrent Involvement of the REL and BCL11A Loci in Classical Hodgkin Lymphoma. Blood, 99, 1474-1477. https://doi.org/10.1182/blood.V99.4.1474

  52. 52. Barth, T.F., Martin-Subero, J.I., Joos, S., et al. (2003) Gains of 2p Involving the REL Locus Correlate with Nuclear c-Rel Protein Accumulation in Neoplastic Cells of Classical Hodgkin Lymphoma. Blood, 101, 3681-3686. https://doi.org/10.1182/blood-2002-08-2577